Originally published: 1952
91 pages | Chapter
28
THE
ETHICS OF REDISTRIBUTION
Bertrand de Jouvenel
|
Fundamental comprehensions develop as people navigate the millions of
words and tens of thousands of books, essays, speeches, and studies on the
subject of self-governance. This doesn't guarantee that such knowledge will
be uniformly applied, or perhaps applied at all, but one hopes it will
continue to be part of honest, ongoing conversations.
By way of example, less than a decade after the
Second World War ended, as the long-term economic and social consequences of
the growing welfare state became plain, significant political and economic
discussions ensued. Many treatises on this subject were written then, and
during the next quarter century. Bertrand de Jouvenel's short study of the
effects of economic redistribution on both society and the individuals of
which it is comprised is an elegant and valuable contribution to this
discourse.
Redistribution encompasses the welfare state in its
greater form, but stops short of fully embracing socialism or communism. The
redistributionists seek to achieve socialism's goals using capitalism's
wealth. The progression is as follows: First, in the early stages of
capitalism, free-market gains allow private enterprise and private charity
to support those who cannot help themselves (the eighteenth century).
Second, as an economy becomes more successful and means are found to tax
that success, government programs come into being, and those who cannot see
to their own care are supported by the state through a social safety net.
This is a political act, as benign as it may initially appear (the
nineteenth century). Third, as the social safety net expands,
347
incrementally,
into the welfare state-where public assistance grows beyond essential
levels, primarily for political reasons-a culture of dependency is fostered,
unintentionally at first, but eventually callously. As well, the welfare
state drives private charitable efforts away thus opening the window even
further for increased state beneficence (the twentieth century). Fourth, as
the welfare state reaches its final stages, equalitarian goals are seen as
possible, and redistribution becomes a barren political tool. The realities
of fiscal, psychological, and overall social costs are pushed to the back
and political meliorism becomes the only measure of value (the twenty-first
century).
Extreme welfarism, termed redistribution, embraces
high rates of taxation, leveled directly on the entrepreneurial class for
the purpose of redistribution of profits to the less well-off. However, it
achieves goals that are the antithesis of its intentions. It kills the geese
laying the golden eggs (entrepreneurs creating profits that can be taxed)
and destroys the character of the society it attempts to make better.
Governmental redistribution of a free-enterprise economy's products is one
of the particular cases where human folly is almost perfectly camouflaged as
human compassion and ingenuity.
De Jouvenel does not attempt to support his
criticism of redistributionist programs with a mass of graphs or charts. His
point is not just that redistribution doesn't achieve its stated economic
goal or its unstated emotional objective, but that it does something more
significant-it changes society and its free-market underpinnings in an
unseemly and ultimately untenable manner, through attempts to alter or even
defy human nature.
De Jouvenel discusses the morality of redistribution not just as it relates
to individual incentive or self-reliance-this had been done by many
authors-but as it affects human society and culture by distorting
macroeconomic realities.
Since the Great Depression, government has
gravitated toward a central role in the remission of poverty thanks to
liberal political activity. This has often pushed out community-based,
private efforts. De Jouvenel observes that over the same period liberals
have disguised as an intellectual precept their quasi-religious judgment
that economic inequality is "intolerably unjust." It should be
noted, however, that contrary to the liberal assertion of capitalism's
putative injustice, the free-enterprise system (when joined with an open
society and the rule of law) actually generates a higher standard of living
at its base than has any totalitarian, centrally-planned, or even
redistributionist economy operating at its highest potential. And, although
the living
348
standard measure is certainly one of the pillars of a
"just" society-it is not the only one. In other words, there is
more proof of the folly of the redistributionists. There is the issue of a
nation's character, the impetus of the people toward charity and assistance
that is in effect until government efforts push such actions aside and
trivialize them.
While a free system of economic interaction
necessarily results in inequalities (as does any collectivist or other
centrally directed system-and a redistributionist system must, by
definition, be centrally directed), almost all of them are positive and
beneficial as is demonstrated by the far higher level of social and economic
advancement achieved by the free economies. These inequalities are a matter
of degree and are based on intrinsic differences between human beings-in
other words, they are the result of normal human interaction. Most important
of all, these differences are accepted, even embraced, by society as
individuals see opportunity for themselves, or especially their children;
the variations are not judged to be destructive or demeaning. (For
additional discussions of inequality itself-a heavily freighted and
oft-abused term-see Friedrich von Hayek's The
Road to Serfdom [Chapter 13], Milton Friedman's Capitalism
and Freedom [Chapter 25] and in particular, Richard Weaver's Ideas
Have Consequences [Chapter 35].)
De Jouvenel comments on those who would tax the
wealthiest citizens, siphoning off their "excess" income in an
essentially confiscatory fashion for redistribution to the less well off.
These theorists assume that the "surplus" dollars in the hands of
the affluent would bring little additional joy, comfort, or substance to
their lives, but would substantially improve the existence of the less
fortunate. In essence, they believe that skimming from the top of the
economic scale to shore up the bottom would result in a more balanced
distribution of essential comforts. However, giving to some what has not
been earned by them is an effort fraught with far more bad consequences than
good-as has been seen in Frederick Bastiat's The
Law (Chapter 7). There is also in such distributions an inconvenient
punitive reality for society's more productive members. As redistributionist
efforts gained traction the discussion of this aspect of their plans was to
be set aside for substantive consideration at another time-a time that has
yet to arrive in liberal circles.
The problem with the liberal's equation, as de
Jouvenel succinctly explains, is that redistributing the "excess"
income of the rich would not begin to substantially improve the economic
circumstances of the economically less well off, much less society as a
whole. The
349
mathematical reality is that while the wealthy have excess
resources, as a group even they do not have a level of income that matches
the designs of the redistributionists. The economic fact is that 97% of all
U.S. income taxes (2005) are already paid by those in the middle and
upper class (those who earn at or
above the median income). Those who earn below the median income-50% of all
earners-pay only 3% of all income taxes. In order to make the lower half of
income earners equal to the upper half virtually all income of the upper
half would have to be redistributed.
De Jouvenel directly observes the point to be
made-the redistributionists do not stop when they've helped those who cannot
help themselves, they intend to level the fundamental economic circumstances
of society en masse. Here redistribution diverges from the social
safety net and expands broad-based welfarism beyond what is economically
tenable. The reason for such expansive redistribution is simple-it is how
the demagogues expect to get public approval for their plans and reelection
for themselves in the bargain-by including everyone on the gravy train who
isn't deemed "rich."
In the determination of the redistributionists,
society's "excess" wealth is essentially all wealth above the
average. Thus, the amount of money that would have to be collected to
achieve this goal would mean increasing taxes all the way down the economic
ladder to the heart of the middle class, a move that would change that
group's lives in an ultimately unpopular manner. De Jouvenel comments,
The idea that sums which pass out of the State's hands come from
above is true as regards only a very minor fraction; and it serves to
obscure the fact that for the most part the buying power which is
redistributed comes out of the same social layers as receive it.
Aside from the fact that redistributionist math
doesn't work, and neither the U.S. Treasury's calculations nor those of the
most liberal Marxist accountant can change it, the lives of all members of a
society-rich, poor, or middle class-are altered when economic equality is
attempted through redistribution. De Jouvenel offers basic observations to
explain these changes.
The first and most obvious effect is that when high
incomes are substantially reduced through taxation, culture, the arts,
education, public service and public charity essentially disappear as personal
350
initiatives because there remains little or no discretionary income
left to support them. The second and more important change is in regard to
the depletion of capital needed for investment, or public improvements, or
any other purpose. Capital and its resultant profit are what drive any
economy. The third, and most profound effect on both the economy and the
citizenry, is the destruction of incentive. If there is no incentive (no
matter what level of society is being considered) there is-nothing.
If accumulated (or "excess") profit is
taxed away and redistributed, the only alternative to replace private
funding for entrepreneurial and cultural objectives-efforts that will not be
given up easily by the public-is the government. But governmental
intervention in either the market or cultural initiatives invites dire
consequences. Without offering extended examples of what would eventuate in
those circumstances one has only to consider the inefficiencies and
intellectual corruption and incompetence of political/bureaucratic oversight
already extant in our own federal and state governments to know what would
eventuate if more power vis-à-vis the economy was turned over to public
and/or political control.
Unfortunately, after tax rates had been raised to
actually allow equalization of (lower) living standards, more and larger
regulatory agencies would need to be established to manage the
redistributionist mandates. This would require government budget increases,
so taxes would almost
immediately need to be increased again across all but the lowest income
levels. This would even further stifle incentive, or the ability to act on
opportunity because the capital that used to be created through private
activity (largely from the savings of the roughly eighty percent of
Americans who are the members of the middle class) would have disappeared,
so additional taxes would be needed to create capital for investment. The
capital pool, however, would be directed and controlled by bureaucrats, and
the judgment, much less the competence, of government employees with so much
power would justifiably be questionable.
The problem in any redistribution scheme is that
extreme taxation suffocates initiative and entrepreneurial activity. When
prospective gains from productive efforts face confiscation and
redistribution, the entrepreneur's incentive is eliminated. Economic
activity eventually comes to a standstill, for a time, and then it begins to
reverse. We ultimately arrive at a terminal condition that is not just
predictable, but inevitable: equality at the bottom. Real-world examples of
this
351
scenario were seen in the Soviet Union until it collapsed under fiscal
burdens it could not support, are currently in evidence in North Korea
(where the population has been reduced to mass starvation) and Cuba, and are
equally observed in China, where a cultural battle (between a government
that professes a belief in de-incentivized equalitarianism and a populace
that does not) may eventually break into a civil conflagration.
De Jouvenel notes that governmental schemes for
wealth redistribution maim and then subvert the sense of social
responsibility and even the human connectedness that constitutes the social
bond. As personal involvement in our own lives is degraded through
governmental direction and control, our personal sense of worth is
undermined, as is each person's sense of his unique value to society. The
standard of living gets lower and lower because there is less and less
income to tax so a greater percentage of income must be taken just to keep
even. As de Jouvenel comments, not only do we not eliminate poverty
through redistribution, we actually institutionalize it, and then expand it.
Supervision of wealth's redistribution demands continued interference with
individual freedom, with negative consequences too broad to enumerate-and
the povertization of all aspects of life: economic, cultural, educational,
social.
De Jouvenel comments regarding why redistribution
retains any credibility in the face of hundreds of years of free-market
economics and thousands of years of experience in the machinations of human
nature. He notes that all of those who consider that income redistribution
will work assume two facts: First, everyone will agree on the method and
level of redistribution and the level and degree of taxation. Second, the
level of productivity in society will not be affected by such
redistribution. On its face, neither assumption is valid. And if neither is
valid, the results obtained will be individually unjust in the first
instance and calamitous to society's standard of living in the second.
At the outset of his discussion, de Jouvenel
summarizes both the history of equalitarian economic methods and the goals
of liberal thinking. He notes that redistribution is not exactly the
stepchild of socialism for redistributionists do not want to dismantle
capitalism or the free market; they do, however, want to achieve socialism's
objectives. Their ambition is to take the profits from those who produce
goods and services-and who presumably spend them frivolously-and give those
profits instead to those who have not fared as well. This approach
352
represents a purely emotional response to the inevitable inequalities of an
economy based on free human activity-a response that attempts to make
liberals feel better about some of the unavoidable, and valuable,
differences among people in terms of talent, intelligence, and ambition, but
succeeds only in making everyone feel worse about the results.
Perhaps more importantly, redistribution also
denies the dignity of labor-all labor. It concentrates on fiscal results,
not on the content of any individual's life. It fails to recognize, much
less comprehend, that inherent differences in ability and gifts are the
foundation of life-and that those differences are not "unfair."
Even if they could be termed such, bureaucratically compensating for
differences in every individual's life would involve judgment, not math. In
that circumstance dissatisfaction with public intuition as to what is fair
would be more certain than the existing presumed dissatisfaction with life
as it is.
On the other side of the equalitarian coin, human
beings are perfectly aware of the benefits, to themselves and to
society in general, of the inequalities among people (otherwise why would
they pay to hear someone other than their mother-in-law sing, or build them
a car, or perform their open-heart surgery?). What the redistributionists
forget is how we will feel when the desirable differences of society and
culture are eliminated and economic opportunity overall diminishes simply
for lack of fuel; as Wilhelm Ropke observed, the fuel of any economy is
profit. When profit is debased through extreme taxation, it descends the
path leading to its extinction. The end result is an ignoble existence for
all of society.
A point should be noted as one travels through the
"inequalities" of an open society: often, modern demagogic
disquisitions on income variations focus on the "rich" and the
"poor," and emphasize the gulf between them. These speakers, for
political purposes, talk only in terms of black and white. What they
intentionally ignore is that the vast majority of the developed world's
population lives in society's economic middle ground, not at the extremes.
The intent of the social revisionists is to
convince the middle class of two things-that they are poor, because they are
not "rich," and that this circumstance is the "fault" of
the wealthy. These tactics are mostly not well received by the largely
educated middle class in America, but they can bear fruit among the less
educated elsewhere. Class warfare, so often attempted as a tactic in U.S.
politics, has never fared well because of overwhelming evidence that
economic status is not static. In fact, there is unrestricted social and
economic mobility, and the American
353
standard of living belies any portrayal
of most citizens as being poor. Finally, and perhaps most importantly, the
American ethic of earning one's place, one's bread, and one's success is
ingrained in our cultural experience and not easily dislodged by promises of
equalitarianism.
De Jouvenel observes that redistribution can appear
superficially attractive, in part, because of the media's distorted focus
regarding the lifestyle of the wealthy. This small but now highly visible
cadre of moneyed persons (allegedly given to cavorting in remote resorts,
driving outrageously expensive automobiles or jet airplanes, and
conspicuously consuming high-priced items in myriad variety) is the perfect
foil for the demagogues. All of this, of course, is simply the media
feasting on frivolity.
The focus on admittedly ostentatious displays of
wealth conveniently ignores what the very well-off do with the vast majority
of their income. The portion that they cannot spend, they invest.
(And let us not forget, the spending and consumption by the wealthy has its
own positive multiplier effect on the economy.) Whether in new companies or
new ideas or in pools of capital that others may use to create more
opportunity, the "excess" income of the wealthy is invariably put
to work improving one thing or another. It also goes toward private funding
of the cultural, public-service, and educational initiatives previously
mentioned. This money does not sit idle inside some mattress. If this
wealth, transformed to capital, is taxed away through redistributionist
schemes, the reserve of assets available to the economy is less. At that
point the economy simply produces less, and that changes everything-not just
the comfort level of one group or another.
Apropos of the supposed case against the wealthy,
de Jouvenel observes:
It is well known that "the people" are less critical of the
high-living
than [are the intellectuals]. . . . [W]hile it still seems right to give [to
the less well-off], the rightness of taking away [from the economically
successful] is far less obvious.
When contemplating the media's exploitation of
the superficial entertainment value of the whimsical minority of the
affluent, it is seen simultaneously that the so-called intellectual elite
experience a judgmental abhorrence of conspicuous consumption (other than
their own). The basis for this is found in envy, or righteousness; the
latter is sometimes even obliquely or inadvertently admitted by those
354
intellectuals engaged in judging. The public does not often share the
intellectuals' distaste, as de Jouvenel notes.
As was observed earlier, class warfare has never
been a successful political tactic in America because parents in each
generation expect their children to be more successful than they were, or at
the very least, to have more opportunity. Therefore, to advocate eliminating
the ability to move up in the world (through the roadblock of redistributive
taxation) or even to imply that each generation cannot be more
self-sustaining, more successful, and more secure, is antithetical to
parental goals for their offspring. It is essentially an insult to parents
and children alike-and is also contrary to the economic and social history
of free-market economies the world over.
De Jouvenel's point that redistribution is not
socialistic in means but is in terms of ends, merits emphasis.
Redistribution's guiding light is meliorism. Under socialism ownership of
private property is essentially to be eliminated, the good will of all
people toward one another is expected, and eventually we are all to get
along so well that the state becomes unnecessary and withers away. These
were the premises of the 1789 French Revolution. But, under
redistributionist schemes, the state has never withered away. It not only
hasn't withered away, it has become more obtrusive (even though its
intention was to become less necessary) in the private and
public sectors as it strives to regulate the distribution of assets,
presumably without the voluntary consent of all parties. The
emotional foundation of the impulse to achieve equalitarian results, as de
Jouvenel intones, rests on a simple theoretical precept:
The rich would feel their loss less than the poor would appreciate their
gain.
As long as the argument is presented in personal
terms (that is, as long as we consider specific individuals whom some think
have too much money, and some who do not have enough) this contention's
immediate logic and appeal can appear obvious and to some individually
arguable. But when the discussion moves to a larger forum, to the society
itself, then as de Jouvenel points out, income redistribution proves to be
immoral, for in practice it would erode the quality of life across all
economic and social strata. The resulting government structure, essentially
totalitarian in nature, would ultimately collapse of its own burdens for the
simple reason that it is irreconcilable with
355
human nature. At the point of
collapse, we would start all over again, man versus man, for as de Jouvenel
notes:
democracy is a regime of well-regulated strife where force is made to
prevail without violence.
But when democracy fails, because people no longer accept its
redistributed fruits as a rational manner of governance or economics, then
violence resumes, as it inevitably must whenever social life goes backward
too far. Intellectual violence occurs initially, with something more serious
following eventually. (For a discussion of governmental power in a democracy
and how that power increases in the name of the people as participation in
the electoral system becomes near universal, see de Jouvenel's On
Power [Chapter 15].)
Interestingly, de Jouvenel initially acknowledges
only in a footnote that what occurs first in the transfer of wealth is the
redistribution of authority, not just resources, from the individual
to the state; yet this is the essence of his intellectual calculations. If
the state takes from some and gives to others, the state will have to
arbitrarily make fifty economic, social, and political decisions with regard
to what it (not the individual) now controls. The resulting fifty
determinations will generate five hundred more questions, ad infinitum, all
to be settled by bureaucrats who have no stake in their answers. These
public servants work their hours, return home, and think (if they are
arrogant) or hope (if they are humble) that they've made the right
decisions. They won't know they've got things terribly wrong until they
stand on the gallows in a social upheaval. They will suffer, not because
they taxed away people's resources, but because they stole everyone's
freedom.
What we witnessed over the course of the twentieth
century, as de Jouvenel observes, was the corruption of political
institutions by means of legislation that discriminated among citizens. When
it is understood that redistribution will not work to effect the desired
result, that it not only doesn't make life better, but makes it much worse,
it will also be understood that
[t]he error must then lie in the original assumption that incomes are to
be regarded solely as means to consumer-enjoyment . . . . [and] the
ideal of income equality is, then, seen to fail by the two standards:
justice
as between individuals, and social utility.
356
Income obviously has purposes other than for
consumption, and to use it as the exclusive means to address raising the
standard of living for some people-whose reason for being
"disadvantaged" may or may not relate to their economic
circumstances-seems a poor bargain. This is especially germane considering
that simply giving people money has historically proven to have more
negative (personal and social) consequences than positive. Income
redistribution creates contradictory effects and costs that are incalculable
except in hindsight. To ignore these results while aiming at emotional or
even righteous satisfaction is why, for example, America's War on Poverty
has failed to change virtually anything for society as a whole or the
conditions of the social stratum at which it is aimed. It has only made
government bigger-certainly not better.
De Jouvenel recognized that living is a social
process, and that feeding, clothing, and housing oneself are merely support
mechanisms. When the benefits of and the opportunities to engage in the
social process are limited, the social life and the individual's vitality
are diminished. The greater the economic opportunity, the greater is the
social life, but that life is rife with inequality. This is a fact of
existence, the reality of which we have accepted for millennia. To try to
eliminate inequality through political maneuvering is to beg the law of
unintended consequences to become the basis of social interaction. What we
must continually recall is that most of life's inequalities are far more
beneficial than derogatory of mankind's existence.
Perhaps de Jouvenel's most optimistic observation
comes toward the end of his dissection of income redistribution schemes.
While discussing the history of taxation and the typical insistence of
rulers that they "know best the common interest, which the individual,
sunk in his selfish pursuits, cannot perceive," he notes the silver
lining in such arrogance:
Indeed, the subject's dislike of taxation has been the means of turning
him into a citizen.
Reflecting one of the themes of First
Principles, de Jouvenel also warns that "[a] society of sheep must
in time beget a government of wolves." We do, indeed, need far more
citizens than subjects to ensure that the state, and the political class (by
means of their own miscalculations or misunderstandings) do not destroy a
social and economic structure that is the best chance for providing the
highest standard
357
of living for all of its citizens. In The
Roots of American Order Russell Kirk succinctly states,
"economic leveling is not economic progress." As the state becomes
stronger, individuals become weaker, not only in relation to the state, but
in real terms as human beings. This is because, as Kirk further observes, we
no longer have those "habits of mind and action that
self-responsibility teaches and which make us individuals;" we only
react to the state.
De Jouvenel's dire forecasts of redistribution's
endgame are not probable in societies where citizens remain vigilant, but
they are certainly possible. Is de Jouvenel crying "wolf" too
loudly? A quick look at Europe's continuing fiscal crises (founded in their
social excesses and declining populations; see Fewer,
by Ben Wattenberg [Chapter 43]), the economic mayhem practiced in Third
World countries, and the U.S.'s looming insolvency based in the
insupportable Social Security, Medicare and Medicaid programs, make a strong
case that redistribution is alive and well-and not just in academic or
political theory.
About the Author
Bertrand de Jouvenel has been termed "the least famous of the great
political thinkers of the twentieth century," but his fame, or lack of
it, may be inversely proportional to the value of his insights. He was
raised in a prosperous literary family who were intensely political and of
ancient French aristocratic lineage on his paternal side. His father was the
French ambassador to the League of Nations after World War I and was elected
to the French senate; his mother presided over an important salon with a
particular interest in France's relations with Czechoslovakia. Born in 1903
in France, de Jouvenel was strongly affected by the rise of Adolf Hitler's
National Socialist Party, the Nazis, and the world war that followed as a
result thereof.
Although de Jouvenel graduated from the Sorbonne in
law and mathematics his career soon gravitated toward economic and political
commentary. His interest in the United States led him to write La Crise
du Capitalisme Americain (1933) [The Crisis of American Capitalism], one
of the first interpretations of the Great Depression. At the time he favored
a strong role for the state in economic matters.
De Jouvenel worked as a journalist specializing in
international affairs for much of the 1930s. He gained worldwide renown for
his 1935 interview with Adolf Hitler. After the outbreak of World War II de
Jouvenel joined the French resistance but was forced to take refuge in
358
Switzerland. There he prepared his most famous work, Du Pouvoir: Histoire
Naturelle de sa Croissance (1945) [On Power:
The Natural History of Its Growth], a harsh critique of the modern
state's authority. De Jouvenel built upon this historically oriented and
profoundly philosophical treatise with several other books over the
succeeding decades.
De Jouvenel taught at the University of Paris and
was a frequent visiting professor at British and American universities. He
worked tirelessly to acquaint the French elite with Anglo-American economic
thought and practices; he was the author of scores of scholarly articles and
books on these subjects. De Jouvenel died in 1987.
Available through:
Liberty Fund, Inc.
Suite 300
8335 Allison Pointe Trail
Indianapolis, IN 46250-1687
(800) 955-8335
www.libertyfund.org
359
|