Originally published: 1962
202 pages | Chapter
25
CAPITALISM AND FREEDOM
Milton Friedman |
Milton Friedman was perhaps the most widely celebrated of the University of
Chicago's eminent economists, one of the numerous Nobel Prize winners in the
school's cadre of creative and penetrating economic thinkers. But Friedman
was not just a theorist; he was an activist, a proselytizer.
Capitalism and Freedom, a title that
expresses an equation basic to free-market economics, is a slim volume,
almost a companion to Henry Hazlitt's Economics
in One Lesson (Chapter 24). But whereas Hazlitt explores the
fundamental relationship between government tax and spending policy on the
one hand and Adam Smith's marketplace on
the other, Friedman correlates the effect of the same governmental policies
on individualism, that is, personal and economic freedom. In the preface he
notes that his intention is to expose some of the myths of government
intervention-including the failure of avowed collectivist policies to bring
us closer to utopia. His purpose is to help us as individuals understand
what we can do to protect and promote our personal and economic liberty.
Throughout the book his encouragement to activism is patent.
Friedman observes that almost invariably it
requires a crisis to energize human beings to act. His goal, therefore, is
to provide tools to deal with economic crises so when something does happen
to motivate us we will be able to address our problems more effectively.
Based on an understanding of economics and human nature these tools could
best be used, of course, to avoid approaching disaster in the first place,
313
but Friedman recognizes that the human condition often gets in the way of
such common sense.
Ultimately, Friedman sought to set a foundation so
that what appeared politically impossible-freedom from overweening
government-would eventually become politically inescapable. For example,
when the socialist ideas of the 1930s and 1940s ultimately failed to bear
any of the fruit that was promised, the need to return to the free market
became palpable. Friedman and his academic cohorts from around the world
provided the philosophy and programs necessary and enunciated some
"rules" to ensure that the freed economic system could function
efficiently. They wanted the system to be understood and embraced on a
personal, a national, and an international level so that collectivist
impulses did not again become the answer to the vicissitudes of economic
activity-whether in a micro- or macro arena.
In order to effect their intentions, Friedman and
his contemporaries gathered in Switzerland in 1947 and formed the Mont
Pelerin Society. Once constituted, this organization and its individual
members publicly called to account the fallacies then prevalent in economic
thinking. They were successful, to the chagrin of their many critics, beyond
almost all expectations, and to them the world owes a great debt-for they
allowed rational economic thinking to re-emerge on the global stage.
Friedman opens his book by dissecting the results
obtained when liberal ideas are put into effect and the reality of everyday
living vis-à-vis these ideas puts a face on the law of unintended
consequences. He finds that the implementation of the ubiquitous liberal
notion of paternalism is almost always demeaning and destructive of
self-confidence and self-sufficiency. Friedman asserts the obvious, namely,
that we are individuals. Not only are we quite able to take care of
ourselves, but we want to. We don't want to be told how or what to do, or be
cared for by government in any measure if we can avoid it. The personal
sense of shame felt by those who first find themselves in the welfare line
is no less prevalent today than it was in the depths of the Depression.
However, those inured to government paternalism and who have been told they
are entitled to welfare are taught to lose that sense of personal dignity
with which we are all endowed at birth. Thus is born, instead, the culture
of dependency. This culture can be reversed-not only for the benefit of the
taxpayers but for the individuals whose sense of life has been so grievously
distorted.
314
Friedman understands the human impulse toward self-sufficiency;
he comments that we would not normally allow or expect anyone else, much
less everyone else (by means of government oversight and intrusion) to do
for us that which we can better do for ourselves. He avers that those who
call for a public effort in this vein do far more harm than good.
Welfarism simply induces people to postpone
deciding when to become responsible for themselves. Friedman's understanding
of these matters reflects his view of government as an instrument of people
engaged in political action-not as an entity apart from them. Government,
which is a continuing personal responsibility for each of us, is our way of
arriving at and implementing policy. Conversely, government does not exist
either to afford faceless bureaucrats the opportunity to meddle in our
affairs or to allow politicians to actualize dreams of how they can
better our lives, or assume responsibility for us (and obtain re-election in
the bargain by means of their often feckless promises).
Central to Friedman's thinking is his largely
successful effort to grapple with a simple question: how can we keep
government bureaucracy and regulation from destroying the freedom on which
America is based? Government can be a threat to freedom because of a
combination of centralized power and the indulgent attitudes, efforts, and
condescensions of misguided politicians and bureaucrats. Friedman offers two
time-tested and effective suggestions to counteract these threats. First, we
should limit the government's reach to those things that either should not
or cannot be accomplished by the private sector. Second, we should design
and implement government policies that directly assist individuals at the
level closest to the citizen in order to avoid the inherent arrogance and
inefficiencies of a distant centralized bureaucracy.
Although the attraction of federal pronouncements
is that they can be uniformly applied across the country, Friedman notes
that the country (much less the individuals within it) is not uniform and
consequently a national system can implode upon local application. During
the last quarter of the twentieth century private sector initiatives and
government programs specifically tailored to local constituencies and
circumstances proved far more effective than any national policies
necessarily designed to address needs in a lowest common denominator
approach. Wisconsin's revolutionary approach to welfare-welfare to
workfare-reduced welfare rolls and brought self-sufficiency and
315
personal
dignity to tens of thousands and was copied on the federal level in the
1990s. This is a prime example of entrepreneurial and innovative government
efforts that are possible when local entities are given the freedom to
address local issues. National pronouncements attempting to resolve local
realities produce uniform mediocrity at best-at great administrative cost.
On the macroeconomic side of his efforts, Friedman
and his partners in the Mont Pelerin Society easily determined where then
current (1940s and 50s) government policies were headed. They understood
equalitarianism as the intended result of socialism and its latter day
cousin, the welfare state. Both are antithetical to freedom. Friedman offers
that people are unequal in diverse ways and their differences go far toward
sustaining the essence and beauty of humanity-not to mention all human
progress. Liberals, who wish to impose an equalitarian outcome, and who
ignore these realities, do so at our peril, for their notions go against the
human spirit and human experience. The dignity of all work and each life is
something that liberals often seem to simply ignore or deny. Their
conclusion, based on their false assumptions, is to force conformity
and results. They thereby give proof that their fundamental premises are
destructive, not just wrong.
Friedman posits that economic freedom does one
simple thing, namely, it separates political power from economic power so
that the two achieve a balance (similar to the balance between the
executive, legislative and judicial branches of government). This is a
sometimes uneasy equilibrium, but essential nevertheless. If the state
(through the legislature and its attendant bureaucracies) subverts that
balance and controls economic relations through political power, the state
becomes a substitute for the people. In this manner the expression of
individuality through free choice is curtailed. During the last half of the
twentieth century it became apparent that legislatures and bureaucracies
felt a need to express their power; the former to maintain their tenure in
office (through the use of both carrot and stick), the latter to exercise
the authority conferred by the former and thus to validate their possession
of it. This exertion of power by political entities reduces the freedom of
the citizen.
An economic model based on voluntary and informed
transactions is what Friedman calls a free, private-enterprise exchange
economy, or competitive capitalism. Friedman notes:
316
Underlying most arguments against a free market is a lack of belief
in freedom itself.
Recognizing that humans are imperfect, governments mistakenly (and often
brazenly) conclude that economic decisions and actions must be made and
taken on behalf of individuals. This suggests not only that ordinary people
are flawed, an assertion with which few would argue, but also that they are
incompetent (until one looks at what human beings have done).
Further, it suggests that politicians and bureaucrats, who are themselves
ordinary humans until they get elected or hired, are more perfect. They are
those human beings wise enough to run the government; they are the anointed
or the chosen. They and their goals are the subject of George Orwell's 1948
novel and screed against totalitarianism, 1984. Orwell effectively
takes collectivism and totalitarianism to their logical conclusions and puts
a conjectural but not unimaginable patina on Friedman's philosophical
declamations.
Friedman, like his colleagues at the University of
Chicago, was not against government; his goal was merely to rationally limit
government's power. With respect to the free market, it is clear that
someone is needed to referee its activities since human beings (subject to
the human condition) will sometimes treat one another unfairly or
dishonestly; however, it must be remembered that the vast machinery of
government, in trying to rectify such idiosyncratic circumstances, is
dealing with an infinitesimally small number of incidents when one
contemplates the billions and billions of honest, open and unregulated
transactions that occur each day. The people, by means of government,
implement rules to moderate their interactions, but the governors often
overreach while trying to rein in the few who are deceitful or dishonest. In
so doing the scope of public authority must not become so enlarged that it
affects or interferes with the 99.9% of life that is not its province. Of
course, government also takes on tasks that are too big, or do need national
unity to perform (such as defense, transportation services, and the monetary
system) and are obvious areas where governmental oversight or coordination
is quite useful. Friedman would be the last to deny the validity of these
public efforts.
How all governing roles play out as well as how the
policies we need to govern ourselves are chosen, in Friedman's view,
reflects "a consensus reached by imperfect and biased [people] through free discussion and
317
trial and error." With freedom, the biases and
self-interests can be balanced out, the mistakes corrected. This is the
reverse of what liberals attempt to force on the public, a programmed
economy supported and regulated by intellectuals who are largely
inexperienced in real-world economics but who think that government should
play a greater role in economic (i.e., private) affairs. In the view
of the liberal there is little room for discussion-and much need for
obedience.
To Friedman, trying to affect our economic
relationships through government intervention is to "make matters worse
by introducing a largely random disturbance that is simply added to other
disturbances." It must be observed that this additional random
disturbance often has no economic basis, thus its effect on the free
market has no rational foundation-it simply skews economic relationships and
causes myriad unintended consequences. Finally, if the government's
theoretical good intentions cannot be effected by means of political
carrots, they can only be implemented with regulatory sticks. In the latter
case the distortions that ensue are obvious. The economy is too large and
too complex to respond rationally to repeated, rapid, minute course changes
through government's intervention either by fiat or even pursuant to
supposedly well-intentioned tax or spending policies. Thus, when government
intervenes in the market the law of unintended consequences takes baneful
effect. Unfortunately, each unintended consequence creates another of its
kind, all to the detriment of free actions being allowed to have their
intended results. The outcome is a descending spiral of interventions with
the eventual goal of each successive government step being to correct the
negative effects of its previous action.
Friedman recognizes the delicate balance that must
be maintained between freedom and power. Political power, no less than any
other kind, corrupts those who hold it. Therefore, politicians must be
limited in what authority is delegated to them. Ultimate power must be
reserved for the people, in whom it resides by virtue of their choices
expressed through voting. If governmental power is exercised according to
democratic principles and kept under control by a system of checks and
balances and frequent elections the relationship between the government and
the governed remains healthy. If governmental power, expressed by elected
representatives, is used for social engineering then government tells people
how they should live their lives. Interventionist ideas such as income
redistribution-one of the fundamental tenets of collectivism and state
welfarism-are often claimed by means of political power to be necessary to
achieve "justice." But
318
Friedman holds that this justice (in the
equalitarian sense that everyone should have the same life) is in direct
conflict with individual freedom. For Friedman true justice resides in the
individual, not the collective. That life is uneven precisely because we are
all individuals is self-evident. Human beings do not voluntarily choose the
same life; why would we want to be forced to?
To Friedman, none of this is to suggest that a
social safety net is either unwise or unjust. But to use an equalitarian
and/or collectivist economic system to achieve a measure of protection for
the less well-off while denying freedom to those who do not need or
desire such protection, is at best naive and at worst intellectually
bankrupt and socially pernicious. Protecting those who cannot protect
themselves is not only worthy, it is a fundamental human response. But
Friedman (and many others who give the concept more than a moment's thought)
understands that people will freely care for one another in the absence of
the state's directed and controlled beneficence. And they will be driven
away from that care as the state intrudes and claims dominion over the less
well-off. Friedman's point is that protecting the freedom of those who are
self-sufficient is as laudable and honorable as protecting the lives
of those who are not.
In Capitalism and Freedom, Friedman
addresses a range of topics, including the education monopoly (a life-long
focus of Friedman's efforts), employment discrimination, labor contracts,
price and rent controls, the gold standard, licensing, and income
redistribution. Although some discussions may now seem dated, the philosophy
and comprehension behind them is decidedly not. Friedman's stimulating
presentation of his main economic concerns-the tyranny of the status quo
brought about largely by redistributionist tax policies and the poverty of
imagination in liberal political circles-still encourage the reader to
ponder not just the issues in the book, but how to participate in the
"big picture" as individuals. Friedman's methods and conclusions
regarding the functions and responsibilities of government remain as valid
as we move into the twenty-first century as when he voiced them almost half
a century ago.
About the Author
Milton Friedman was a senior research fellow at the Hoover Institution at
Stanford University until his death in 2006, and a professor emeritus at the
University of Chicago (from which he retired from
319
active teaching at the in
1977). He won the Nobel Prize for economics in 1976 for his part in the
study and extension of monetarist theory. Friedman was born in New York City
in 1912 and relatively early in life he came to view economic and social
freedom-understood in terms of the free market and secure rights to private
property-as intertwined inextricably with broader personal freedoms. His
career followed the evolution of this field of study.
He began his professional life in economics after
obtaining a BA from Rutgers University, an MA from the University of
Chicago, and a Ph.D. from Columbia University. He was one of the founders of
the Mont Pelerin Society, the group that re-focused on classical economics
in the vein of Adam Smith and helped debunk collectivist ideas at the
conclusion of World War II.
Perhaps most notable regarding Friedman's efforts
was his life-long intense interest in education and educational policy.
Friedman viewed the educational monopoly enjoyed by public educators and
their teacher union cohorts to be one of the great "crimes" of the
American experience. That he devoted so much effort to this nearly
half-century passion requires that anyone who considers his life and
accomplishments in the field of economics must also investigate why
education was an equal enterprise in his journey (see <www.friedmanfoundation.org>).
This is more than a worthwhile tangential effort for anyone interested in
where education has been, or is going-and everyone should be.
Available through:
University of Chicago Press
University of Chicago
Chicago, IL 60637
www.uchicago.edu
320
|