Originally published: 1959
284 pages | Chapter
26
THE ROOTS OF CAPITALISM
John Chamberlain |
As his book attests, John Chamberlain loved America. He devoted much of his
professional efforts to an explanation of the philosophy and machinery of
modern capitalism, the foundation of America's freedom and security, so his
readers could appreciate what we have created-good and bad. He became an
expert in dissecting the connection between government and the free market,
how we legislate and adjudicate, how we accomplish our duties and expand our
opportunities, and most importantly, how the excesses of government we visit
upon ourselves affect everyday lives.
In The Roots of Capitalism, Chamberlain
investigates the origins of the entrepreneurial economic model and the free
enterprise system. But he considers that paradigm as square two; he starts
his discussion at a point before the issues of government or the free
market arose. Like so many others, he begins with the premise that a free
society must be predicated on a moral framework and an understanding of
man's free will. Without a moral foundation and the freedom to choose to
make it work, citizens in their ordinary lives cannot trust the system, nor
are they likely to trust one another.
To make any sense of the idea of morality, it must be presumed that
the human being is responsible for his actions-and responsibility cannot
be understood apart from the presumption of freedom of choice.
For Chamberlain, like Frank Meyer (In
Defense of Freedom [Chapter 10]),
321
if human beings do not have the
option to make bad choices they will not understand the content, and
necessity, of good choices.
After setting the stage with these fundamental
premises Chamberlain analyzes the market on which a free society must be
based. He demonstrates that a free market exists when free choice is
exercised in both the application of labor and the disposition or
acquisition of property. Without these freedoms we reel toward
collectivism-embodied first in control of economic life, then dominion over
our personal lives.
Yet, even before these freedoms can work together
there must be a physical foundation, for man is a physical animal. That
foundation is private property. Chamberlain engages in a root investigation
of property, which he found to be the basis of liberty. (For an expanded
account of this essential relationship see Richard Pipes's Property
and Freedom [Chapter 11].) It is beneficial, as many of the authors
studied in First Principles recognize, to return to the foundations
of modern social relationships before examining their more complex
interactions. For Chamberlain, economics was the study of the significance
of ownership-"the right to dispose of [or acquire] a good or
service."
If there be any question of the human impulse to
ownership and the right to the free exchange of property Chamberlain gives
stark examples of what people have historically risked for these basic
entitlements. What he offers is a sketch of the conditions that slowly, but
inexorably, led to the freedom we experience today-a freedom attained only
with blood.
Chamberlain's model is eighteenth-century France
where freedom of action was essentially destroyed by the arrogance of the
monarchy and the "intellectuals" of the period, and virtually
inflexible economic rules were put in place. The French had implemented over
two thousand pages of regulations covering the textile industry, with dire
consequences for those who ignored the precepts of the government. Yet
people would still risk all for their perceived right to economic freedom.
As Chamberlain recounts,
For breaking [textile] regulations some 16,000 people were either
executed or killed in armed brushes with government agents. And . . .
on a single occasion, seventy-seven people were sentenced to be
hanged for breaking economic regulations, fifty-eight to be broken
on the wheel, and six hundred thirty-one were sent to the galleys.
Yet for the sake of "natural liberty" men continued to break the
rigid mercantilist laws.
322
These brutal statistics found their genesis in
the Enlightenment-a label that becomes an oxymoron when some of its effects
are considered. The Enlightenment's foundation was rationalism, a process
distorted by an excess of logic over experience. Essentially, rationalism
contended that if the human mind could define a practical solution to the
difficulties of human interaction, implementation was the only impediment to
a more perfect world. The problem, of course, is that human beings are not
always rational. It is not that we are wholly irrational very often, but our
thoughts and hopes frequently do not mesh well with the surrounding real
world. While this may be a minor inconvenience, the more important issue is
that what is rational to one person can be insanity to another. Thus there
was not and cannot be agreement on what might be the best course in any
situation. Far more to the point, no one can know which course of action
will ultimately prove most advantageous. This simple fact led to freedom of
choice being the only reasonable method to arriving at best solutions for
whatever problems arose (these best solutions will, as well, change over
time as facts, imagination, and outcomes determine additional course
changes).
The masters of France did not see it that way. If
the resolution to circumstantial social and economic differences was only a
matter of making a choice those in power would make the decision (often in a
corrupt fashion-after all, they were only human, and French). This, of
course, was nothing more than a dictatorship, or perhaps more accurately, a
kleptocracy. However, no matter how directly and surely choices were made
there were always those who disagreed and believed in their right to act on
their disagreement. Perhaps most importantly, there is a more subtle and far
more remarkable point to be found in the murderous statistics cited by
Chamberlain. It relates not to the simplicity of the penalties (death in
most cases, implemented to encourage adherence to the regulatory decrees)
nor to the authoritarian reduction of choices to only what was commanded by
those in power; it was found in the massive resistance expressed by the
people in spite of the lethal punishments. Freedom of choice and action were
more important, more core, to these citizens than their very lives.
The American experience of this era was the
opposite of the European. The Founders of the U.S. constitutional system
were wise enough not to fashion a blueprint for all social arrangements.
They understood that freedom would open a pathway to choices that would
bring us to functional, but varied, conclusions about how to make economic
323
and political decisions. Chamberlain voices concern regarding how this approach had been insidiously undermined in
modern times. For example, he believes that the federal government's
regulation of the private sector under the auspices of the commerce clause
in the U.S. Constitution has resulted in far more negative than positive
consequences. This has been especially noticeable in the twentieth century,
where such intervention is often effected through the courts as well as
Congress. This continuing battle between government and the free market has
changed both American society and the business climate to such an extent
that the whole struggles to be recognizable as a market capitalism model
anymore.
Chamberlain's commentary in The Roots of
Capitalism contends that a sense of equalitarianism and political
correctness (long before that term came to the fore) underlies melioristic
government intrusion into the marketplace. It is enforced by means of the
legal system-a system that operates in an economic vacuum and is often
arbitrary and rarely evidences an understanding of the existence of vast
vertical and horizontal market forces. Unless this process is reversed,
eventually the market will become so skewed we will experience nothing but
increased government intervention as each special interest or constituency
makes its case-to the point of substantial economic contraction or even
social instability.
Milton Friedman's comprehension of the effect of
these government actions, delineated in Capitalism
and Freedom (Chapter 25) and written contemporaneously with The
Roots of Capitalism, is equally stark and apprehensive. He observes that
government's eventual authoritarian form results in continued attempts to
rectify by further legislation and judicial and bureaucratic intrusion that
which had already been warped by previous attempts to control market
sectors. These results were the inevitable consequence of what the courts
and Congress had incrementally (and in theory, innocently) constructed.
Chamberlain, like Friedman, holds that followed to its logical conclusion,
such programmatic excesses as he witnessed in the 1950s would simply result
in the disappearance of the free market as any sort of effective independent
mechanism. That this has not happened to the extent Chamberlain feared is
more a testament to American economic ingenuity and the massive size of our
economy than any reluctance on the part of bureaucrats or politicians to
intervene in our economic relationships.
As a business realist Chamberlain helps define how
human beings express their motivations in the marketplace. He focuses on the
con-
324
tinued striving of individuals to upend any equilibrium in the world of
commerce (to their advantage, of course, but then obliquely to the advantage
of the whole system) as they try to better their products, their prices,
their sales, and themselves. In order for this atmosphere to allow each
person to act as he deems fit, even to chase his dream, freedom and a free
market must exist-with a minimum of government's direct interference and
indirect meddling via regulations and bureaucratic overseers.
Chamberlain saw politics as it is-a game of power.
In point of fact, political power is correctly to be defined as interference
with social power.
It may be even more useful to reframe his proposition at its basic level
and change Chamberlain's observation slightly to say, "political power
is correctly to be defined as interference with social rights."
Stated this way, the juxtaposition is more palpable, and perhaps more
accurate. It isn't just that free citizens have social power; it is their
rights to freedom of action and freedom of choice that
are more sacrosanct-no matter how much actual power they possess. For a
quite profitable and detailed investigation of Power-a topic that must be
understood in all political and economic contexts-Bertrand de Jouvenel's On
Power (Chapter 15) covers this subject from serf to king, citizen to
president.
Chamberlain reserves some of his harshest criticism
for government regulators who do not understand competition (which is both
vertical and horizontal) and how it functions in conjunction with the
imperative of freedom of action. Writing in the 1950s, he cites the
competitive challenges to then-corporate behemoth United States Steel as an
example. Chamberlain notes that U.S. Steel did, at one point, control some
two-thirds of the domestic steel market. Federal regulators took note and
salivated at the opportunity to dismember the company because of its
dominant position. They could not, however, alter U.S. Steel's corporate
structure or operations at the time because of various political, economic,
legal, and social realities. It was fortunate that the regulators (who as
do-gooders did not look so much forward as downward from their exalted perch
as public servants) found themselves thwarted. What they might have
done, to the detriment of the system-through the precedent that could have
been set-was instead accomplished as it should have been, based on the facts
as they evolved in a free-flowing and open market.
325
Lacking business acumen, or patience, the
regulators neither understood nor sought to comprehend that U.S. Steel faced
competitive pressures from four sources. Each of these sources was
individually more threatening than all the government interventionists
combined. Big Steel, as the company was known, battled the other one-third
of the industry; it fought foreign competitors; it had to innovate as fast
as specialty producers, who were improving products as quickly as finished
sheets rolled off U.S. Steel's lines; and most importantly, it faced
vertical competition from wood, plastics, other metals, and the new
composites that researchers were developing. Within twenty years of the peak
of its power U.S. Steel was on the ropes as a major producer of anything;
within forty years the company had disappeared from the corporate landscape
and the New York Stock Exchange, all without government tampering. Whatever
the company's complacent and even presumptuous executives didn't inflict on
U.S. Steel by failing to manage its workforce or modernize its facilities,
the free market did. Big Steel was held up to the light by its competitors
and found wanting and the free market "dismantled" U.S. Steel more
thoroughly and decisively than the government ever could have hoped to.
The governing impulse, somewhat curbed in an
earlier time, today enjoys much freer rein. What is frightening to American
business is the government's markedly increased regulatory and
administrative power to meddle. And, perhaps more harmful, is the changing
of tax policy or the regulating premises mid-stream, so that the business
owner, the consumer, and the taxpayer are prevented from planning with any
certainty. This causes economic caution and reduces the impetus of those on
all sides of the economic equation to assume risks (the consumer doesn't
purchase, the producer doesn't manufacture, the entrepreneur doesn't invest
or invent, the innovator doesn't experiment, etc.). The stifling effect on
the economy is palpable and, over the long term, dangerous. Finally, it
should be ironically apparent that there is only a random and small chance
that ignorant and inexperienced legislators or government regulators, or
even judges will impose workable, much less salutary, restrictions on the
market.
Considering these circumstances, the suggestion
arises that before we ask the government to manage anything else, let us
first look at the results of what it has wrought in the past: public
housing, public education, public health, and public transportation to
mention a few. Chamberlain notes that government has historically been quick
to step in, but slow to understand the market and even slower to step back
326
once engaged. After all, government regulators have jobs to do and if they
don't regulate something they cannot justify their existence. So they act.
How Chamberlain would have cringed had he seen the government's case against
Microsoft in 1999 and again in 2003.
In his book, Chamberlain does not shrink from
attacking the sweeping notions of the collectivist society. As noted
earlier, he observes that one regulated sector of an economy inevitably
begets another; the conceit of government becomes operative through
incremental, ostensibly innocent or even theoretically beneficial regulatory
steps, until liberty is lost. In an avalanche each snowflake claims
innocence.
Chamberlain's commentary foretells of government
potentially in extremis when it takes its "omnipotence"
seriously-an act which is itself the highest form of intellectual
corruption. In The Roots of Capitalism one can foresee the
progressive destruction of a society by reason of government incompetence,
then corruption-as it tries to cover its tracks and defend its
failures-resulting in increasing paternalism and equally intense resistance
thereto. Eventually, government becomes paralyzed because of misguided
policies that largely work against one another. The effects of unchecked
intellectual corruption-an administration's increasing insistence that it is
right as the evidence is ever stronger that it is wrong-lead to government
that cannot do good or prevent bad. It is reduced to picking up the pieces
of its last fiasco or putting out the fires created by its never-ending
remedial efforts to fix what it has already broken-while blaming the
market, the business person, or the public for its failures.
The downward spiral begins-always-in intellectual
hubris, based first in ignorance, then arrogance, then power, and finally
presumed omnipotence. Lest anyone believe that omnipotence is not claimed in
American government-simply review the tax code, our educational mandates,
our commercial or environmental regulations, or any of the other 10 million
pages of federal edicts.
Although the modern regulatory state is portrayed
as harmless as it insists on helping those whom the bureaucracy says cannot
help themselves, or stops those whom it contends are harming the public, the
effects of its programs are larger than their material or even philosophical
content. They concern how we govern ourselves and what we think of ourselves
and our lives. Those who don't understand the potential for violence or
catastrophe when a populace is denied its liberty and property-through the
incremental destruction of freedom portended in the ever-increasing
nanny-state-will pay a price that is
327
not yet imagined in America. Corruption
can take many forms: the intellectual corruption of statist or
"therapeutic" liberal endeavors intends benevolence, but in terms
of human behavior, achieves an end far different from its goal. Left
unchecked, such intrusions can grow in devastation equal to that experienced
in the revolutionary histories so well documented by the authors reviewed in
First Principles. The future that is seen by these
authors-particularly that of John Chamberlain-is not a predictive
insistence, but it is a caution founded in history and facts.
About the Author
Born in 1903, John Chamberlain attended Yale University where he acquired a
taste for literature and literary pursuits and thereafter spent his life
writing about things important to him. In 1932 he
published his first book, Farewell to Reform, the story of American
enterprise from 1880 to 1920. During the bulk of the Depression, in order to
make a living, Chamberlain wrote a daily book review for the New York
Times. But his true love was investigating the permutations of modern
free-market capitalism and its partnership with individual liberty.
Chamberlain came to classical liberalism through a
personal process, which he revealed in his autobiography A Life With the
Printed Word (1982). Like many intellectuals of the 1930s he briefly
flirted with socialism, but he was brought back to his devotion to classical
liberalism when he read Albert Jay Nock's Our Enemy The State
published in 1937. From the mid-1930s through the end of his career, the
book reviews he wrote-probably the part of his career for which he was best
known-along with articles for Fortune, Life, and numerous
other publications, were combined with the publication of several more
books. He served on the editorial staff of both Fortune and Life
between 1936 and 1950. The Roots of Capitalism, perhaps his finest
effort, was published in 1959. He was a longtime member of the American
Conservative Union's board of directors. Chamberlain died in 1995.
Available through:
Liberty Fund, Inc.
Suite 300
8335 Allison Pointe Trail
Indianapolis, IN 46250-1687
(800) 955-8335
www.libertyfund.org
328
|