Originally published: 1962
229 pages | Chapter
10
IN DEFENSE OF FREEDOM
Frank S. Meyer |
Like all political constructions, conservatism has many facets. As was
noted in the introduction to First Principles conservatism is not so
much a philosophy as it is a movement, and a way of thinking. Over
time-several centuries-the various methods and foundations of conservative
thought have been tested in the political marketplace. Ultimately, two
approaches to governance evolved, both of which embraced truly conservative
thinking and each of which supported the other. The first was called
conservatism, the other libertarianism. But there were differences; some
were significant variations regarding what government should and should not
be able to accomplish. These variations required cross-pollination, or at
least mutual recognition, in order to make both processes serviceable and to
allow them to be applied to everyday realities. They also needed the
restraints each faction forced the other to consider. The two were far
better off together than separate.
In the 1950s Frank Meyer blended these two
approaches in one of his signal philosophical achievements. This melding was
called "fusion." Classical liberal traditionalists, the
philosophical descendants of Edmund Burke (known today as conservatives) and
Libertarians had been partially at odds for many years, and Meyer knew that
their methodological and substantive differences needed to be resolved
before the theories both represented could or would be a force in
philosophical, economic, or political conversations. Meyer's fusion helped
make the American conservative movement intellectually and politically
viable.
155
Meyer starts, as Lord Acton does (Essays
in the History of Liberty [Chapter 9]), with the Libertarian premise
that an individual's freedom, not the needs of society, is the
"decisive criterion" of good government. The conservative heirs of
Edmund Burke had taken a slightly different tack; they posited that society
was an organic or living reality to which the individual's subordination,
within limits, was necessary in order for the whole to function. For the
followers of Burke defining exactly the dividing line between individual and
societal rights was where a philosophy of governance served a purpose.
Meyer's fusion reflects his understanding, in line
with Burke's, that the lessons of the past, which had coalesced into rules
of human behavior and interaction (traditional or "classical"
liberalism), could not be minimized for they were hard fought and logically
established. As well, however, the imperative of change and the needs of
each individual (Libertarianism) could not be eschewed at the behest of
government no matter how much tradition was involved and no matter how
important society's claimed preeminence. Through the generations since
Burke's time the West experienced a continually evolving world where
government expanded for no other reason than it could. The individual's need
and right to protect himself from that ever-encroaching Leviathan had
become, for Meyer and the Libertarians, a given. As Meyer observes, the
necessity of controlling government both intellectually and actually, is
simply a continuing obligation of the governed. They cannot rely on the
governors to do this for them.
The philosophical conjunction of traditional or
classical liberalism and Libertarianism was achieved through Meyer's
process. This was not because the followers of either viewpoint necessarily
felt they needed each other but because their philosophies were mutually
sustaining. The classical liberals understood the need to value history's
lessons (its "prescriptions"); the Libertarians expressed the need
never to lose sight of man's first goal-his freedom. It was, and still is, a
good fit. The Libertarians continually remind us to control government to
protect the individual's freedom; conversely, government, from the classical
liberal viewpoint, is to continually strive to order society to protect
everyone's individual rights. Liberty under law on one hand, freedom from
unnecessary or arbitrary control of any ilk on the other. That, in Meyer's
hands, became the paradigm. How well it actually works is up to us.
156
As he defines the two branches of conservatism
Meyer dissects government and contends in opposition to the thinking of
Enlightenment-era liberals that there is no "deified will"
embodied in the state. The liberals insisted otherwise; that the state, not
the individual, was the supreme "good." For Meyer the state has no
purpose that can be exalted above mankind; the state is an empty vessel that
only the people can fill, idiosyncratically, based on the vagaries of life.
He maintains, with obvious validity, that truth can never be achieved with
finality. Instead, each generation must test the truths of the past and, in
so doing, find its own verities and discover its own errors. Man's relation
to man and to society never ceases to evolve and it is thus a given that the
test of truth is not logic or authority but experience.
The bulk of Meyer's commentary on the freedom he
observes embodied in the fluid relationship between tradition and
individualism appears in the main essay of this abbreviated collection of
his publications. Because of his personal history it was almost imperative
that Meyer go through the intellectual exercise that was to result in his
contribution to conservative practice. That journey greatly benefited all
conservative thinking.
Meyer came to conservatism and his concept of
freedom through the same fanatical mid-twentieth-century communist route as
did many of his intellectual contemporaries, and his ultimate
anti-communism, anti-utopianism, and anti-totalitarianism were equally
fervent. Meyer's earlier philosophy, before he enunciated the imperative of
liberty, is relatively easy to comprehend. The rationalist goal of all the
collectivist intellectuals (that they could judiciously design and
forcefully implement a perfect society built with imperfect humanity) led
them to authoritarianism and, for some, communism. But their intellectualism
and the results that many of them eventually saw in the totalitarian
marketplace brought those grounded in the real world to understand their
basic mistake; that is, their failure to accurately account for the human
condition-both its positive and not-so-positive facets.
They ultimately came to grasp that neither equality
nor human perfection could be attained by fiat. They also arrived at the
understanding that human inequalities, as measured by virtually all
criteria, were not only not bad but were the foundation of all advancement.
These inequalities license progress and its consequent betterment of life
for everyone. The real crime according to Meyer and his formerly
157
collectivist colleagues is the stifling or extinction of man's freedom-not
the fact that society is rife with inequity. For Meyer,
freedom is no more nor less than the possibility-and responsibility-to
choose. Freedom is the essence of the being of man, and since all
social
institutions are subordinate to men, the virtue of political and social
institutions should be judged by the degree to which they expand or
contract the area of freedom.
Meyer's point that "all social institutions
are subordinate to men" is one found repeatedly throughout First
Principles. It is one not to lose sight of as the various political
creations, programs, and philosophies are encountered down through the
centuries. The ease with which men can manipulate life for their own ends
results in less confidence in the design of any governing entity and
more concern regarding the open and enforceable rules put in place to
constrain mankind's or its ruler's impulses and power.
Meyer's second step in his analysis of freedom is
to determine the climate under which liberty can flourish. Like all
classical liberals he understood that civil society must have as its first
premise an ethical base. If there are no "understood" rules by
which civil discourse can proceed with comity, then it is folly to try to
write or legislate those necessary to govern human interaction. Conversely,
if we live in a moral society, then the number of rules, the number of
points where government needs to step in to officiate are minimized (but not
eliminated, for human foibles always exist).
For Meyer, the creation of the "state,"
the ultimate referee, furthers the (very limited) governmental aim of
ensuring an atmosphere of freedom in which people can choose and achieve
literally anything they might imagine. The people have to act in a virtuous
manner so that the necessity of any state intervention will be minimal;
insofar as they do proceed in a moral fashion they need neither guidance nor
control. Virtue, to Meyer, is a condition, a "state of grace"
toward which humanity must always strive. Though ephemeral it is
nevertheless the only rational goal of society. Virtue has religious,
altruistic overtones, but it does not necessarily rest upon formal religious
practices or any one faith. It really rests on man's relationship to man.
Finally, Meyer returns to the concept of equality,
which to conservatives means both the protection of everyone from coercion
(from
158
being forced to do or be something other than what one's nature
demands) and ensuring to everyone an equality of opportunity. For society,
these two pre-conditions inevitably end in unequal results. Inequalities in
individual attributes, performances, and outcomes flow from each person's
genes, circumstances, and character. It is not within a government's
capabilities to ensure an equal result for each individual and that surely
must not become its goal. In the real world inequality of outcome is
far less fearsome than inequality of rights.
Apropos of this principle, Meyer focuses on what he
calls the Myth of Society: that man engages in political union to serve the
whole. As noted above, Meyer contends that the relationship is the opposite:
that political society's purpose is the maximizing of freedom for the
individual through mutually accepted minimal limitations on personal
actions. This stance, often called libertarianism, reflects a fundamental
belief in both the individual's natural rights, and reason, coupled with
experience, as the interpreter of those rights as they are translated into
action.
Perhaps most important for Meyer, there is no
morality attached to freedom. Freedom is not a vehicle toward good; it is a
condition or status. Freedom used badly or for bad ends is no less freedom.
If man cannot choose to use freedom for his worst ends there is no
opposition of values enabling him to know what his best may be. Thus,
society affords no prospect for progress without the freedom to choose, the
freedom to act upon the choices made, and finally, to take responsibility
for the consequences of our actions.
For Meyer, the state exists to preserve the
individual's freedom to act and to be free from coercion by others, either
collectively or individually. Therefore, the only legitimate uses of the
state's power are to defend tranquillity from without or within and to
pursue the administration of justice; i.e., the determination of where one
individual's rights end and another's begin. To exercise these minimal
powers, however, requires a dangerous concentration of authority; as a
result the state must be limited in its range of power. Individuals or
collections of individuals can and must commit themselves to performing
virtually all societal functions not granted to the state thus keeping the
state from growing simply through opportunity or convenience. The American
educational system would be a prime example of what happens when the state
initially becomes involved and then, by means of its gathered power, morphs
into a Leviathan that can be stopped only through pitched battle.
The goal of society, once limits are set, is to
maintain a free order while pursuing virtue; and virtue, in a social
construct, is defined as
159
little more than the Golden Rule. The two branches
of conservative thinking-the traditionalist (which emphasizes evolved virtue
[truths learned through experience and time]) and the Libertarian (which
dwells on freedom), can thus meld into one because their foundations are
complementary. Being free is not antithetical to virtue, and being virtuous
is not destructive of freedom. For Meyer, the ability to choose good or bad
is the only method by which we might freely achieve virtue. Conversely, of
course, Meyer argues that virtue cannot be decreed-not by agreement, not by
democratic mechanisms, and not by means of a dictatorial leadership. He
writes of truth and virtue as metaphysical and moral ends, and freedom as
the political prerequisite to achieve them. Truth and virtue can only be
obtained by individuals-the "state" can only be virtuous if its
members are, and it cannot be virtuous if the citizenry is not.
Following this reasoning, Meyer sees government as
properly having a minimal role; that is, to deal only with essential aspects
of a free society. The problem with this approach is that as admirable as it
appears on paper it often does not adequately take into consideration man's
innate ability to act at cross-purposes with himself. Our inventive genius
for stupidity and/or inattention creates demands to expand government's
minimalist role, especially in our current no-fault politically correct
society. However, for Meyer, it is imperative that government not manage our
individual lives just as we should not individually control others or allow
them to dictate to us. Sometimes, though, the effects of human perversity
become so intolerable that government, of necessity, must intrude. The
unfortunate sequence of events that seems to inevitably follow, and the
point at which minimalist intervention exceeds its proper bounds, occurs
when government's role in any aspect of social intercourse becomes
domineering and-worst of all-permanent. (Again, public education comes to
mind, as does today's welfare model, and soon our healthcare system.)
The important point nowadays is that government's
supposedly "essential" activities grow in tandem with the
intellectually fashionable aversion to relying upon personal responsibility
to ensure individual well-being and societal tranquillity. Meyer's reasoning
relates to the fact that we have appended a Bill of Rights to our
Constitution, but no Bill of Responsibilities. Meyer repeatedly notes that
although a perfect society is obviously not within man's capability, getting
as close as we can is one of our responsibilities. Even though
perfection is unattainable, striving is not futile as there are many good by-products
160
derived from our efforts. Giving up on individuals
and instead placing controls on everyone by means of government proclamation
leads to an agglomeration of government that becomes counterproductive,
oppressive, and ultimately, totalitarian.
Meyer sets the stage for understanding why the
individual is the foundation block of society and why individualism is the
antithesis of the welfare state. In In Defense of Freedom, he
describes the necessary political mechanisms that have been formed out of
the American experience which have allowed us to partially weather the
collectivist storm thus far. However, as one can tell from Meyer's premises,
the war is far from over.
About the Author
Frank Straus Meyer was born in 1909. He attended Princeton University and
later Oxford College in England where he became a leader of student radicals
and a member of the Communist Party. He worked within the party for fourteen
years until he experienced his anti-totalitarian epiphany, the result of
reading Friedrich von Hayek's The Road
to Serfdom while serving in the U.S. Army in World War II. After the
war Meyer broke completely with the Communists and spent time exposing their
methods and machinations. He served as an editor and columnist at National
Review for many years and was a leading force in the effort to bring to
fruition what became known as "fusion"-the joining of the major
elements of American conservatism. Frank Meyer died in 1972, an icon among
American conservatives.
Available through:
Liberty Fund, Inc.
Suite 300
8335 Allison Pointe Trail
Indianapolis, IN 46250-1687
(800) 955-8335
www.libertyfund.org
161 |