Originally published: 1835 & 1840 (in two volumes)
317 pages (abridged) |
Chapter 8
DEMOCRACY IN
AMERICA
Alexis de Tocqueville
|
America, in all its guises, has fascinated Old World intellectuals since
well before 1776, and French nobleman Alexis de Tocqueville was no
exception. As a young man he was particularly captivated by the allure of
our nascent democracy. Though his 1831 visit to the newly formed United
States, when he was but twenty-six years old, lasted only nine months, his
account of that journey continues to provide intriguing insights into the
challenges inherent in a Jeffersonian democracy. There are few men who are
more often or more widely quoted than this connoisseur of the American
experiment.
When Tocqueville arrived in the New World the
United States had recently celebrated its fortieth anniversary as a nation.
The last of the Founders were passing into history and the focus was no
longer solely on the new government but on the new country and the new
citizenry. The states were yet mostly equal partners with the administration
in Washington and economic and social relationships were beginning to form
patterns. The free market was still the wild card. As would become clear
over the years, capitalism itself (as much as the citizens) needed rules to
constrain its darker impulses. But most Americans were too close to their
own world to see what they had wrought. It took the independent and quite
sophisticated view of a foreigner to comprehend all the potential-good and
bad.
Tocqueville's own aristocratic family had suffered
greatly during the liberty, equality, and fraternity of the French
Revolution of 1789 yet he held no enmity toward the egalitarian effects of
majority rule or democracy. Instead, he was fascinated by the question of
what a democracy
135
could be now that he well understood from his own country's
revolution what it shouldn't be. And although the ostensible purpose of his
trip to the New World was to study the American prison system his ultimate
goal was to view constitutional government firsthand:
It is not, then, merely to satisfy a legitimate curiosity that I have
examined America: my wish has been to find there instruction by
which we may ourselves profit. . . . I sought there the image
of democracy itself . . . in order to learn what we have to fear
or to hope from its progress.
What is unique about Tocqueville is his ability
to get over the giddy feeling that the fraternity of democracy, coupled with
the rule of law, is designed to foster. As a result of the French Revolution
he plainly understood that human beings do not always strive for the good of
their fellows. No matter what system of governance is chosen it has to be
designed to restrain man's sometimes dismal nature. Tocqueville also opines
that the well-being of any society achieved by equalitarian (as opposed to
egalitarian) efforts is at risk if its citizens do not recognize the
corrosive effects of too much equality, or equality that is forced, not
earned. Finally, Tocqueville understood the nature of power (even if
achieved by democratic means) and its effect on those who suddenly find
themselves in a position to wield it.
In America, Rousseau's theoretical tyrannical
majority (a majority that could make decisions without considering the
rights of, or its duties to, a mostly powerless minority) is hypothetically
stymied by the Constitution. The design offers protection for most of the
citizenry's natural rights and puts forward some political guarantees. But
that document does not dictate human character; that is, citizen
individuality or morality,
or perhaps most important of all, human courage. In other words, Tocqueville sees the first chinks
in the practice of American freedom. They relate not to the documents or
their direct governmental functioning but to the effects of a democratically
imposed uniformity and striving for an intellectual notion of equality.
Tocqueville is troubled that a social or corporate conceit might arise
vis-à-vis the value of equality that could destroy individuality. As
equality's leveling effects (intellectually) insist on uniformity the
ultimate result can be complaisance bred of felt individual impotence or
unimportance, or even just the obligation to go along.
Breaking out from this smothering compliance can often be termed, by
those in power, as anti-social with every stigma such
136
a contention evokes.
This is “soft” tyranny, that only grows in power with each
instance of acceptance. The
first evidence of soft tyranny is when speech is curtailed.
This is where political correctness begins to blossom.
A corollary to this concern lay in America's vast
commercial potential. Tocqueville sees the titanic American economic nation
earlier than many others. Yet in that national possibility-encompassed in
unimagined expanses of land and natural resources and pure enterprise-he
also sees a tendency toward leveling that might command a repressive
political/psychological unity in the name of progress. Tocqueville sees a
uniform intention to achieve material success and thus an American society
where its economic goals become increasingly both homogenous and
overwhelming. Tocqueville fears a populace bereft of intellectual, cultural,
or social diversity if all are solely focused, as they seemed to be, simply
on profit and temporal abundance. What he didn't witness and therefore
didn't count on was what could be done with those profits by private
citizens, which as the years passed became a massive amount of individual
activity not directed at further material success but aimed at
fellow-citizens and society as a whole, and at sheer personal enjoyment,
which is notably unequal.
Tocqueville worries further how America will
ameliorate the potentially harmful effects of a constantly encroaching
commercial power on both the freedoms and the rights of the minority. He
sees that an overt but potentially false majoritarian intellectual or
philosophical hegemony by those in positions of power, commercial and
political power together, is possible and is thus a concern. Tocqueville
warns of a "government for and of the people, but not by them." It
should be remembered that Tocqueville visited America in the midst of
Jacksonian democracy's flowering when ideas of egalitarianism and majority
rule were approaching their apogee. However, the representative facet of
governing, where wisdom is to be interposed between citizen democracy and
laws, he sees as potentially being subverted. He foresees commercial
interests clinching the social and economic bit in their legislative teeth
to impose supposedly majority concepts that do not necessarily have majority
backing or real majoritarian interests at heart.
And Tocqueville's fears did come to fruition to an
extent by the turn of the twentieth century when the so-called robber barons
seemed to operate by their own rules. At that point a counterforce arose in
the form of Teddy Roosevelt's trust-busting efforts. The checks and balances
worked, albeit slowly as they must, first, because the society is so large
137
and fluid, and second, because when action is taken too precipitously the
law of unintended consequences comes into play. Often that law brings forth
results that are more destructive than the ill that is to be cured.
On another front, as Tocqueville also anticipates,
some ideologues were extending the idea of majority rule and its egalitarian
intentions to irrational conclusions that had nothing to do with democratic
representation and everything to do with politics. Tocqueville predicts that
if
"intellectuals" can posit that our equality before the law also
creates an expectation that we will treat everyone's talents and
capabilities as equal, then someone would do so. Equalitarian elitists do
not stop with the premise that the citizen's vote or opportunity is to be
equal. They contend that the usefulness or value of a citizen's capabilities
is to be determined, to a greater or lesser degree, not by the free market
but by the state. Ultimately, this social equalitarian view embraces the
charge that we should strive for equality of result-particularly economic
result-and not just equality of opportunity. This call for equal result is a
dishonest distortion of the Constitution's specific call for equal treatment
and equal opportunity. Yet this demand continues unabated when demagogues
posture as the supposed friends and guardians of human dignity. (James
Madison, primary author of the Constitution, foresaw the probability of a
call for equal result by means of the Constitution's insistence of equal
opportunity, and addressed this possibility directly in Federalist #10.)
In pursuing this long train of suppositions and
possibilities Tocqueville comments at length upon the dynamic relationship
between equality and individuality. He repeatedly suggests that
individuality is at risk of being reduced to a mere concept by the leveling
effects of majority rule. He sees not just the tyranny of the majority but
the hegemony of the median-a social attitude against exceptionalism
or excellence or even just the right to be different. For Tocqueville, the
danger is one of fostering a docile citizenry that will ultimately come to
accept an equalitarian dictatorship formed out of intellectual pretensions
simply because it doesn't know any better, or is afraid to challenge it.
Yet Tocqueville also notes that Americans appear to
distrust “intellectual systems” or theoretical solutions to real-world
circumstances, preferring instead to concentrate on facts.
This observation fits well with his and many other author’s notions
that centralized government, founded on broad intellectual principles, works
poorly in practice because every rule, every
decision, every pronouncement—whether administrative, legislative,
or judicial—does not fit either every person or every circumstance.
Distrust of theoretical systems also reflects
138
the nineteenth and twentieth-century dislike of the Enlightenment’s good intentions, which
almost invariably devolve into one-size fits all systems. The
theory is, this system will work because it is rational.
The problem is everyone is not rational in the same way; as well,
human beings are not easily corralled into lock-step fealty when it comes to
choices. Thus good intentions
are not sufficient to govern, we must also look at results, and if the
results do not match the intentions, then the value of the intention or any
action that springs therefrom, speaks for itself.
To bring this concept forward to the twenty-first
century, one might consider the effects of political correctness or its
cousin moral relativism. A society where differences are seen as merely
opposite sides of various coins and right and wrong essentially do not exist
can ultimately lead to anarchy, or meekness in the face of despotism. As
emotionally satisfying as social homogenization may seem at first, progress
is never grounded on sameness but rather on unique and valuable differences.
As fearful as some of Tocqueville's premonitions
are he also argues the other side. He sees that an ability to ameliorate
coercive majority rule (to ensure it would not become majority tyranny)
rests in three uniquely American factors: strong and independent local
government, the advantages of a socially mobile society, and the benefits of
unfettered economic opportunity used to achieve self-sufficiency. As
Tocqueville predicts, the ever-expanding grasp of federalism still fights
for intrusive control at all levels of local and state government. He sees
it as up to the citizenry to resist this intrusion into local and state
affairs and incursion into the lives of individuals. He isn't sure the
populace is up to this task because of its timidity in the face of idealized
equalitarianism. Tocqueville is not so much pessimistic in these musings as
realistic. He could not foresee how Power could be controlled by the
populace but he is encouraged that in America's design there was at least a
mechanism for allowing that to happen.
In America's early years Tocqueville did observe a
social structure that was fluid, a condition which served as a bulwark
against class jealousies and warfare both then and now. He found that the
vast majority of the people were "sufficiently well-off to desire
order, but not so well-off to excite envy." With respect to government
he states that the American electorate is not degraded by habits of
subservience to laws and officials, especially to the nobility and a king as
was the case in monarchical Europe. He sees that this condition could
continue so long as the public, through its right to vote, chooses the laws
and people to whom
139
obedience will be due. In other words, Tocqueville sees
democracy as potentially self-correcting with regard to most of the
indignities and insanities that exist when power is concentrated, but only if the populace
remains vigilant, as citizens, and does not become complacent, as subjects.
His theories of what could happen, on the positive side, however, do
not leave him sanguine. His understanding of human nature is his overriding
concern thus he expresses anxiety about majority rule.
Tocqueville considered local administration a
powerful safeguard against corruption and oppression by either the national
or state governments. He knew that a centralized administration simply
couldn't run the whole country, even a nation as yet as uncomplicated as the
United States was in 1831:
However enlightened and skillful a central power may be, it cannot
of itself embrace all the details of life. Such vigilance exceeds the
power of man. And when it attempts unaided to create and set in
motion so many complicated springs, it must submit to a very imperfect
result, or exhaust itself in bootless efforts.
These comments are inevitably an oblique denunciation of the ultimate
authority over every facet of life claimed by the French socialist state
that had evolved in the aftermath of the Revolution of 1789.
Tocqueville sees a partnership in America that was
lacking in Europe:
When the [American] state seeks to act, within its own limits, it is
not abandoned to itself . . . the duties of private citizens are not
supposed to have lapsed because the state has come into action:
but every one is ready, on the contrary, to guide and support it.
Yet, irrespective of any real or imagined
citizen/government partnership Tocqueville still predicts the accretion of
federal power through the "need" for policy to be guided in areas
such as defense, transportation, and commerce that are inevitably national
in scope. He expects these activities of the national government to
proliferate and expand into control of ever more minor and local aspects of
governance in order to achieve political or economic goals. It is an
incontrovertible fact that bureaucracy feeds on itself. When we see today's
federal
140
government reaching down to the local level on issues such as
welfare, health care, and education, and achieving ever smaller results, it
is clear Tocqueville's fears were well founded.
Tocqueville, remembering the excesses of Rousseau's
idealized omnipotent democracy, expresses his own intellectually healthy
fear of the majority:
If it be admitted that a man possessing power may misuse that power,
why should not a majority be liable to the same reproach? Men do not
change their characters by uniting with each other. The power to do
everything, which I should refuse to one of my equals, I will never
grant to any number of them.
Today, following the lode opened in
Tocqueville's observation, we have seen those who wish to govern too often
simply demand of the voters "Trust me." We hear the media or
candidates
themselves speak of "mandates" when an office-seeker wins 55% (or
even less) of the vote. Gaining 55% of the vote still leaves a substantial
minority not necessarily in agreement with any supposed mandate. Although
the intentions of those elected are often "good," Tocqueville knew
there is too much risk in granting to any majority a blank check uncoupled
from fiscal, personal, or corporate responsibility. This result was seen at
the beginning of the twenty-first century as the newly majoritarian
neoconservatives engaged in political sleight-of-hand that resulted in
fiscally capricious programs such as the Medicare prescription drug benefit
or the No Child Left Behind education mandates.
Following this vein Tocqueville comments on the
potential for excessive legislative and executive reach and the means by
which such excesses could be curbed. He observes that his fear of the
legislative majority or the electoral mandate is somewhat attenuated by the
power of the judicial system. He views the ability of both elected and
appointed judges to determine a law unconstitutional as one of the most
powerful barriers that had ever been devised against the tyranny of
politicians and political assemblies. Tocqueville and others were correct in
viewing the judiciary as an antidote to oppressive legislative or executive
grasp. They foresaw judicial control of extreme insults to the Constitution
as a given; what they did not foresee, however, was the gradual debasement
of Constitutional tenets through judicial interpretation and activism, and
an omnivorous bureaucracy.
141
The compulsion of some in the judicial
establishment to make judgments based on a "new era" or a new
understanding often amounts to nothing more than the promulgation of law
from the bench. In the end such actions are just as effective in changing
the plain meaning of constitutional protections as would be any amendment to
the document itself. This is primarily a twentieth- and twenty-first-century
phenomenon that has yet to be resolved and can only be addressed by an
informed and active electorate.
As observant as Tocqueville is about so many
negative possibilities he nevertheless sees an oppressive majority and an
ever-intrusive federalism coming to fruition only in stages. In his view
there is ample opportunity to employ counter-measures to retain what might
be lost. For Tocqueville there is as much hope as gloom in all of this. If
the inherent effectiveness of citizen activism is realized it will act as a
check on the potential oppressions of the governors; the people can maintain
control of their own destiny and Tocqueville's fears of the slippery slope
to electoral or actual tyranny can be abated. Unfortunately, in significant
measure the course and consequences he presciently predicts have come to
pass. On paper we still retain a democracy but as always the devil is in the
details. In America, many today feel the need to reassert the importance of
Tocqueville's countervailing "details" to lessen the hegemony of
base equalitarianism fostered by an increasingly centralized government.
To a large extent the ability of the citizenry to
control its government rests on what the people know. Tocqueville understood
this correlation and dissects his era's media-newspapers and pamphlets-and
their ability to encourage debate by spreading the word. He sees writers and
editors as capable of creating groups of people who "will never meet,
talk, study, or explore together, but who will nevertheless act as political
blocs," (often today through political blogs). His observations are
probably even more germane in the twenty-first century when the Internet and
the media-much proliferated in terms of variety, numbers, and availability
to citizens-operate so as to create even larger groups of unconnected but
like-minded people. Ultimately, as Tocqueville foresees, we have created
"mass civilization."
Tocqueville opines regarding the media: "The
evil they produce is much less than the evil which they cure." Some
today would disagree, arguing that the immense amount of information-along
with
concomitant misinformation and disinformation in quantities Tocqueville
never imagined-actually has a negative effect. The sheer volume
142
overwhelms
the individual's capacity to comprehend even a portion, much less all that
is available. A resulting inability to decide what is true, or truly best,
ensues. The ultimate effect of this mass of media may be closer to
intellectual paralysis than the systemic practicality Tocqueville hopes for.
Tocqueville ultimately recognizes the power of
ideas to thwart government compulsion, especially in cases when the media
fails the public or even joins the tyrannical majority:
Force is never more than a transient element of success, and after
force, comes the notion of right.
Ideas Have Consequences
(Chapter 35), The Commanding Heights
(Chapter 29), The Road to Serfdom
(Chapter 13), and other books reviewed in following chapters repeat this
theme and offer myriad examples of its truth. Ideas are the salvation of the
worried, the tool of the oppressed, and the bane of the powerful. They
ultimately right our wrongs.
The latter portions of this abridgment of
Tocqueville's Democracy in America deal to a large extent with
observations of the effect of majority rule and democracy on the
personalities, habits, outlooks, achievements, and goals of American
society. Tocqueville goes a considerable distance to demonstrate the direct
relationship between the extent of democracy and what we would call today
the "dumbing down" of citizens. Tocqueville predicts that as both
democracy and commerce proliferate the individual can become marginalized
with population growth and the need for overarching government uniformity in
an increasingly diverse and complex society. On one occasion he discusses
the potential for people to relinquish their individual character and thus,
ultimately, their intellectual franchise:
When neither law nor custom professes to establish frequent and
habitual relations between men, their intercourse originates in the
accidental similarity of opinions and tastes. In democracies, members
of the community never differ much from each other, and naturally
stand so near that they may all be confounded in one general mass.
In juxtaposition to this, however, is the
dynamism Tocqueville sees in American ambition and, especially, in its
commerce. Without
143
excessively belaboring the obvious, it remains true that
his sometimes schizophrenic approach makes one wonder whether we are as
monotonous and bland (and perhaps doomed) as he sometimes describes us. Is
it true that ever-pressing majorities homogenize us and cause our
differences to be trivialized, or is our individual freedom of choice and
action always the antidote to mass society taking over?
Tocqueville's overall observations on the
differences between democratic freedom and democratic despotism-the latter
expressed as the leveling effects of democracy gone too far-are as cogent
and vital today as they were when he wrote them:
There is nothing more arduous than the apprenticeship of liberty. It is
not so with despotism: despotism often promises to make amends for
a thousand previous ills: it supports the right, it protects the oppressed,
and it maintains public order. The nation is lulled by the temporary
prosperity, which it produces, until it is roused to a sense of its misery.
Liberty, on the contrary, is generally established with difficulty in the
midst of storms: it is perfected by civil discord: and its benefits cannot
be appreciated until it is already old.
Tocqueville warns that the greatest danger to a
failed democracy is not anarchy, as would seem natural, but totalitarianism.
"Nations are led away [by the principle of equality] to servitude,
without perceiving its drift." Although anarchy is what appears to be
happening initially, totalitarianism eventuates because the people's will is
broken by anarchic actions; they give up and give in, in order to obtain
security. In the face of anarchy security is more valued than freedom.
As noted previously, Tocqueville foresees two great
dangers for democracy: the accretion of central power because of
administrative necessity, and the self-censoring fear of speaking up in an
equalitarian society because we judge our opinions as no more valid than
anyone else's. Here are the seeds of today's political correctness. These
forces inure people to docility, and often strike them mute. Tocqueville
proposes active freedom of expression as the remedy for this disease. He
ultimately conveys confidence in the power of ideas and in the vehicle that
carries those ideas, the human spirit. This is a lesson that, two centuries,
later, still transfers well from Tocqueville's musings.
Tocqueville introduces us to a thousand truths
about a democratic society. All are tied up in the details of
self-government exercised
144
with care and corruption, fidelity and perfidy, by
a people continually redefining and reinventing themselves. His time-honored
observations on the human condition and its antidote, individual liberty,
still define a practical framework.
About the Author
Born in 1805 into the French nobility, Alexis Charles Henri Clerel de
Tocqueville was precocious, aggressive, inventive, and self-sufficient. His
family was exiled after the revolution of 1830, but Tocqueville stayed in
France, swearing allegiance to the new government. He obtained a French
government grant to study the prison system in America and traveled around
North America for three-quarters of a year during 1831-32. Publication of
his preeminent work, Democracy in America, in two volumes in 1835 and 1840,
made him both famous and sought after. Subsequent to the success of this
book he led a rather quiet life, marrying an Englishwoman and accepting a
series of minor posts in the French government. He forewarned of revolution
in 1848 and endured the massive upheavals of 1848-49. He retired from public
life in 1849 because of his poor health, suffering from a disease of the
lungs. He moved south to a more temperate climate on a doctor's orders.
Alexis de Tocqueville died in 1859.
Available through:
Penguin Putnam, Inc.
375 Hudson St.
New York, NY 10014
ecommerce@us.penguingroup.com
145 |