Originally published: 1776
590 pages | Chapter
12
WEALTH OF NATIONS
Adam Smith |
Adam Smith is to capitalism as Thomas Jefferson is to freedom. And Wealth
of Nations is to free-market economics as the Declaration of
Independence is to American sovereignty. Smith's understanding of commerce
and human nature and his conclusions regarding the structure and future of
the British mercantile system (which was rife with protectionist
fabrications in the eighteenth century) are as germane and applicable today
as they were to the emergence of capitalism more than two centuries ago.
Modern economic life was born with the Industrial
Revolution and virtually all of the elements of present-day commerce were in
evidence in England by the 1700s. With as much accuracy as if he were a
contemporary lecturer in economics Smith writes of markets, trade,
incentive-all the ingredients of economic discourse-and the limits of
government. He discusses taxes comprehensively delving into how, when, by
whom and to what degree they could profitably be levied for both the
government and citizens. Finally, he writes about people-the good and the
bad of the human condition. Smith's goal was to establish why it is in the
best interests of both the governed and the government that consumer
sovereignty rule economic markets.
Although Smith did not enjoy our ease of access to
information he cites commercial statistics and cost data (i.e., the costs of
doing business) to substantiate his conclusions for England and the European
continent. The wealth of detail, which Smith was thoughtful enough to use
somewhat selectively, dates from as long as centuries before he
183
wrote. This
makes his work as exhaustive as it is easy to comprehend, not just in its
logic but also in the value of his inferences.
Smith begins his exploration of economic substance
one step beyond the infancy of human endeavor. He assumes that the existence
of private property has been intellectually accepted and economically
justified; thus he does not attempt to defend it as an institution. He found
the investigation and explication of property in the works of John Locke
both logical and rational. (Locke's template, from which Smith partially
assembled his own theories, can be found in The
Second Treatise on Civil Government, [Chapter 1]). With that
foundation, Smith jumps directly into a consideration of human nature to
discover why progress (literally the "progression of
improvements") occurs. He sees the catalyst of progress in human
dissatisfaction with any status quo. People's ingenuity moves them
from the unsatisfactory to the better and toward the unattainable best.
Without the achievement of perfection the process neatly self-perpetuates.
A small digression may be useful at this point.
There is in the modern era an often-expressed complaint from the so-called
intellectuals (who may over-think such things to a remarkable degree) that
there is a malaise infecting the body politic. The suggestion is that our
society has produced an overabundance of almost everything-except happiness.
They claim there is a general dissatisfaction with life in spite of how much
we have achieved both materially, spiritually, and intellectually. The
logical conclusion for this group is that we have accumulated a lot but
given not enough. Once they determined that our dissatisfaction results from
the fact we have not offered enough of ourselves and our resources to make
the world a perfect Eden (in spite of the fact that the United States is the
most generous nation on earth-now or ever-and is considered the
"can-do" society by almost any measure used) their solution is to
take from those who have been successful and award that bounty to those who
are not as well-off, their theory being that will make both groups happy.
They contend we have not given enough because we are too free to keep the
fruits of our labor and that this freedom needs to be curtailed. The proof
of this need, they claim, is in the pudding-we have all this success yet in
the realization of happiness, emblazoned in the Constitution as our inherent
right, we have failed.
The problem with this straightforward declamation
is that it ignores three points; the first is that the allegations of
discontent may, unfortunately, be politically not sociologically motivated
and constructed
184
(another result of manipulation by or by means of the
media); the second is that the Constitution doesn't promise happiness, just
the right to pursue it. And happiness is achieved in the pursuit, not only
in the momentary attainment of something that pleases us. Jefferson and the
other Founders knew this thus their intentional phrasing. The third reason
that a distorted claim of unhappiness can be made but not substantiated is
man's well-understood uneasiness; this element has nothing to do with
parsimony.
Man is uneasy because he sees
opportunity-constantly. It is his uneasiness that drives the progress we
obtain. The problem is that our uneasiness doesn't disappear with any given
success, at least not in the long run. It is in our very nature to be
displeased with the status quo thus it can be claimed that we are
unhappy when we are not, we are simply exhibiting the human genius for
improvement embodied in curiosity, inventiveness, cleverness, and diligence.
It is this aptitude for change and invention that pushes us to move on from
even the most spectacular success. That is a human condition not the result
of some systemic malfunction or failure. Thus changing the system without
changing the underlying factors of human nature actually changes nothing.
That people can be happy in spite of the fact that they are not wealthy,
that they can be happy because they understand the benefits of
inequality among human beings and they recognize that none of those
inequalities stop them from aspiring is the starting point of human
comprehension. If the rules of the game are changed so that to aspire
becomes a bootless effort then lives change fundamentally.
When we see a psychosocial inquiry into why modern
man, whose life is abundant, is "unhappy" perhaps we should
question the question. What is certain is that the romantic
prescription-that because we are alleged to be unhappy with what we have we
might as well give it for the benefit of some other group-misses the point
of man's journey by a wide margin. Man is not unhappy with what he has
achieved, but he does get confused if not disgruntled when someone suggests
that removing the fruits of his labor from his bank account will make him
happy. He sees such an action making him quite the more unhappy from where
he supposedly is in the first place. This of course does not even begin to
deal with the question: if economic well-being does not make those who
earned it happy what is there in the wealth itself that will make those to
whom it is given any happier than those from whom it is taken? For the
redistributionists life is seen only in terms of mathematics-never as human
reality.
185
Freedom is the real issue in these discussions; it
is freedom that scares the twenty-first century liberal as much as it did
the eighteenth-century Jacobin at the time of the French Revolution. The
fact is that freedom doesn't scare human beings in general, and that is the
point of First Principles.
Let us return to Adam Smith's more practical
contentions: In any economic paradigm, relationships are primarily defined
and operate in terms of two human characteristics: striving for power
(through competition, not as megalomania) and the power of aspiration. In a
free market progress is achieved by human endeavor to remove
dissatisfaction-the lure of our aspirations-and change is the only constant.
Striving for power, to be "the best," creates continual
competition-to surpass one's rivals. This can, but rarely does, result in
excesses of one sort or another. The reason these excesses are rare is found
in Smith's concept of "enlightened self-interest"-a brilliant leap
of understanding and expression and the first part of Smith's definition of
a workable economic model (the other part being the free, unconstrained
market).
Smith's model for enlightened self-interest is the
person who realizes and acts on the fact that he must satisfy his customer
to ensure repeated patronage or garner a positive reputation to enlist new
business. He must offer fair value at a fair price. Enlightened
self-interest is nothing more than understanding that "I will do well
for myself, if I do well by others." The philosophy of capitalism is
that both parties to any transaction view themselves as being better
off when the bargain is struck-and once the deal is complete both actually are
better off based on their individual circumstances and goals. There is
mutual benefit from and mutual consent to the transaction. The consumer has
parted with his money, but received something more valuable-to him-some need
is fulfilled that his money as a commodity could not satisfy. The producer
has sold his product or service, paid his expenses, taxes and employees, the
cost of which is hopefully less than the amount gained from the transaction,
and is ready to begin the cycle again. The negative stereotype-that somehow
the consumer is being short-changed by paying money for something he wants
and only the producer profits is bogus and survives only in a demagogic
atmosphere. The consumer profits by attaining his goal more easily by using
money made engaging in some other effort. He then exchanges that money for
whatever it is someone else makes that he desires more than his pocket full
of earnings (and that he could not likely efficiently produce himself
anyway).
186
The unplanned cooperation when engaging in economic
self-interest becomes reciprocally beneficial, and those benefits are not
unnoticed by human beings. Social progress is palpable in this paradigm and
Smith's discernment and explanation of enlightened self-interest, though it
was little more than observing what was happening on the ground, was
nevertheless near revolutionary in his era. However, self-interest as a
concept also needs to be taught, evangelized; it is not always either
self-recognized or self-effecting. The carrot of gain is worthwhile, but the
stick of forfeit for behavior that is counterproductive is necessary as
well. In making his observations, Smith discusses all aspects of free-market
discipline.
Modern
anti-capitalists use Smith’s concept of enlightened self-interest in a
derogatory fashion; most importantly they leave out Smith's
modifier--enlightened. They focus
on self-interest in order to condemn capitalism as selfish while asserting
there is nothing enlightened about it. But Smith was not advocating social
policy or suggesting how people should act, he was making real-world
observations—that people do act in their own interest. Smith
also was not claiming that self-interest uniformly has beneficial effects; he only observed that self-interest is
not by definition,
bad, certainly not in a free economic setting.
Theoretical systems postulating economic symmetry,
equality, and presumed beauty don't change men from their nature no matter
how much we'd sometimes like that to be the case. Men embrace useful versus
futile behavior not by the implementation of arbitrary utopian direction,
but through individually comprehending the benefits of the former and
detriments of the latter while maintaining their intrinsic self-interest.
This enlightened state-self-learned through experience and observation-is
what encourages unplanned and mutually beneficial cooperation. Idealized
systems that attempt to force an equalitarian goal with wholesale uniformity
cannot achieve the flexibility to account for individual differences in
personality and skill, thus for their implementation they require, first,
constraints, then control. Unfortunately, the nature of human affairs,
economic affairs in
particular, cannot be remedied by government, or even more remotely, by
politics. We can only design society to work within the constraints of human
character and human nature. To attempt more is to reach for a fantasy.
In the end if free-market competition goes awry
private or public counter-measures become necessary. If the problem becomes
significant
187
government is available to step in as a referee. But Smith notes
how well the free market works, referencing the thousands and thousands of
transactions occurring each day (in his time) without a hitch. When
we compare that with the few misdeeds that make headlines each year
it is easy to understand that people not only want a sound and fair system
within which to operate but that they will make every effort to ensure that
happens. The lawless confusion of previous eras was unpleasant and
unrewarding and wholly without any security-thus the unpopularity of
anarchy, whether commercial or civil, and the acclaim of its antidote,
enlightened self-interest.
Underlying all of Smith's writing is his view of
human nature, both how it works and how it does not. From his acceptance of
the existence of property rights to the gains in economy achieved through
the division of labor to the establishment of the marketplace (where the
pieces and players can freely interact), his systemic logic remains
unchallenged. The market is the stage upon which all activity takes place,
but in Adam Smith's play the director is the invisible hand of voluntary and
enlightened human interaction. Smith mentions the invisible hand only once
in Wealth of Nations but it is the part of the equation necessary to
understand why liberty and free markets work, and collectivism (or
centralized control) does not. The vast interrelationships inherent in any
economic structure cannot even be comprehended much less charted, and even
less, dictated, by any single or group effort-such a feat is well beyond the
power of any human mechanism. The alternative is free interaction. In a
system of free interaction decisions are made based on each participant's
view of his own well being and his personal desires. The invisible decisions
and processes not only allow this unimaginably complex system to function
but to work to the advantage of everyone.
Smith could assume nothing about his readers'
intellectual or economic sophistication. Writing at a time when the market
itself was in its infancy (although it should be noted that in 1720 London,
more than fifty years before the publication of Wealth of Nations,
there already existed over 20,000 privately owned shops [and thus Napoleon's
later derisive sobriquet that England was but a nation of shopkeepers]) and
universal education was still a century in the future, he addresses both the
learned and the economically illiterate using a rigorously logical but
necessarily pedantic approach. Put simply, Smith was composing from a
vantage point not just unappreciated by even above-average individuals but
actually unknown
188
to virtually all of his audience. In today's often
contentious political climate enlightened self-interest and the unplanned
symmetry of the market's invisible hand can be distorted for electoral
gain-and to the detriment of both the voters and the economy-thus the need
to reconsider capitalism and the free market in the more elemental form that
Smith describes.
At the end of his practical and philosophical
investigation into capitalism, Smith arrives at "opulence" as the result
not the goal of human ingenuity and interaction. (In his day, opulence meant
personal and national commercial success, not gaudy over-consumption.) How
one economic system or any class within an economic system arrives at
opulence was grist for Smith's mill.
While explaining the intricacies of commerce Smith
takes the road less traveled. His survey of human beings and their nature
differs from the morally needy characterizations that were embedded
in the darker notions and severe punishments of the religious dogma in vogue
during the Middle Ages and in practice in Puritan England. He views mankind
not as venal and sinful but as worthy of trust-both collectively and
individually. His insight was simple: people would effect the common good
through their recognition of common goals. In this respect, Smith expresses
not social Darwinism (the charge of those who view capitalism as a predatory
enterprise), but enlightened self-interest. In his estimation monarchical
authoritarianism impeded man's ability to reach his full potential. Personal
freedom coupled with economic freedom was the best guarantee of social
progress.
While Smith believed in the need for government he
saw government as the arbiter not the director of social interaction.
Because human folly cannot be eliminated (no matter how much we've learned
about right and wrong) Smith understood people should not set up government
in an attempt to control every potentially negative human action. Rather,
government should have mechanisms to deal with grand or petty aberrations
when they do occur. Having a policeman on every corner to prevent human
perfidy is neither achievable nor workable. In Smith's estimation the
(free-market) playing field would be largely self-leveling-because of the
effects of reciprocal self-interest. If certain individuals were hard to
deal with the market would limit their success as recognition of their
practices spread.
There was little anonymity in the eighteenth
century-population was low and concentrated, travel limited. Reputation was
of paramount importance. Admittedly, however, there was also significant innocence,
189
even gullibility, as the era's new products were offered. But for
Smith it was up to the people to sort all that out-not the government, for
neither the government nor its functionaries were wiser in these matters
than were the participants. The participants had far more incentive to
protect themselves than did bureaucrats who, even in Smith's time, were
alternately indolent and authoritarian-and you could never be sure whether
Dr. Jekyll or Mr. Hyde would show up to perform his bureaucratic duties on
any given day.
Smith's basic insight into economic life admits of
a succinct summary: free activities and free relationships best guarantee
that all economic elements (both human and commercial) will balance one
another to maximize progress. If we let government or some other
monopolistic force tamper with any aspect of free economic life (absent a
direct need to protect the citizenry) there will be widespread side
effects-generally to the detriment of those not doing the tampering.
Furthermore, we cannot view economic activity in a vacuum; there is a
cascade effect no matter how trivial governmental intervention may seem.
Smith's assessment of the role of government was as
concise as his explanation of how the free market works. The time and place
where government is beneficial is generally threefold: to protect citizens
from foreign invasion, to establish a system of civil justice for relations
between citizens, and to construct and maintain public works and
institutions that individuals cannot effectively create on their own. A
subset of these necessary institutions relates to dealing with fraudulent,
destructive or dangerous economic activity, oftentimes (but not always)
criminal in nature.
The universal bugaboo of capitalism and its
essential freedom, whether in the time of Adam Smith or today, is the
shyster or the charlatan. This is an area in which government plays an
important but secondary role. The bad actor, who distorts the existing
economic balance, is often held up as exhibit one in defense of government
control or intervention in a free-market economy. But the scoundrel, the
fraud, and the cheat are not capitalists in the honest sense; each is simply
a thief. (Sometimes, indeed, he is not even a thief for it is not gain that
drives him but the adventure
and use of his own faculties in outwitting his fellows, or in driving away
his boredom, that is the impetus.) We need not alter capitalism to prevent
their misdeeds; we alter their relationship with their fellow economic
actors by removing them from the system. This allows capitalism to work
properly. When a bad apple is in the barrel we simply remove it hopefully
before it corrupts the
190
other apples. To deal with fraud and its cousins
Smith recommends only two remedies: individual responsibility and the
government's enforcement of clearly defined criminal statutes.
Smith's position is that personal responsibility is
the first line of defense in all economic relationships. "Let the buyer
beware" is one of many familiar aphorisms coined to make people
cognizant of their role in protecting themselves. It expresses the
obligation of individuals to use good judgment. Smith argues that it is our
duty to act on the fact that if something sounds too good to be true it
probably is.
Smith observes an unfortunate but simple fact
regarding human institutions: it isn't capital or capitalism or the free
market that is bad. Neither is democracy or unbridled free speech
deleterious. It is always individuals who create the distortions. Moreover,
there is not even a hint that if the government were to control the economy
or any other aspect of our lives that frauds, cheats, or even incompetents
(who appear so innocent, but do so much harm) would cease to exist, or, more
to the point, avoid government employment. There would simply be no way to
prevent such people from worming their way into positions of authority. Both
moral and intellectual failings are human, not institutional, and are as
commonly found in government workers-especially government workers with
great power and indubitable job security-as in corporate chieftains or local
shopkeepers who have to answer in the marketplace. After all, each of us
suffers in equal measure from the human condition.
Over time Smith's canny observations about human
nature became useful in creating solutions to those instances when
capitalism did, indeed, suffer from its own excesses. However, the focus on
the difficulties and criticisms of the free market often ignore the obvious
and incredible progress for the societies in which it operates. The aberrant
minuscule part of the story of capitalism becomes the flea that wags the
tail that wags the dog. The public perception of materialistic
perfidy-because of the existence of capitalism's infrequent failings and the
omission of its achievements-is intentionally created and encouraged by the
few. Such a view is often fostered by unjustified and erroneous media and
political tumult and results in ingrained and sometimes ubiquitous, arrogant
hectoring. This negative campaign works for both the press (to increase its
own profit by encouraging public conflict) and the political hand-wringers
who view, almost wholly through ignorance and emotional misapprehension, any
individual failure as total or systemic failure, and a demagogic opportunity
to encourage their own political
191
success. Reading Smith's views re-engages
the citizen in the reality of free enterprise without politicizing the
subject. That is fruitful today almost beyond measure.
The ultimate form of governmental economic
intervention in the twentieth century and the polar opposite of Smith's
investigations was pervasive socialism. In defending socialism its
proponents claimed that government can best control the multiple and
ever-more-complex forces of commerce and do so to create the greatest good.
In fact, it turns out that just the opposite is true; the more complicated
an economy becomes the more necessary is the freedom of individuals to act
in their own interests. Any centralizing force becomes less able to direct
all segments at all times in any efficient or productive direction.
Socialism was and is every free marketer's worst
nightmare. Its horrible reality took root in those places where the most
egregious forms of governmental monopolistic controls already existed and
thus did the most harm where it could be least tolerated. These excesses, as
awful as they turned out to be in the twentieth century, were a perfect
counterpoise to the value and utility of the free enterprise system. The
pendulum thus swung back and socialism suffered accordingly. Although Smith
foresaw a glimmer of socialism's economic madness, its salient
characteristic-state ownership of production processes and facilities-was
far enough from his world of monarchy that its eventuality was not central
to his investigation. However, its ultimate place in the potential chain of
events was certainly evident in his logic.
Socialism's twenty-first-century progeny, state
welfarism, is the subject of other chapters in First Principles.
Welfarism's characteristics and effects are so similar to those of socialism
that the consistencies become a continual theme. As will be seen, when the
fundamentals of economic understanding are followed during the period
between Smith's eighteenth century and our twenty-first neither the
community of concerns nor the array of misapprehensions regarding government
intrusion into the marketplace suffers any significant mutation. Nor does
the discussion abate.
In Wealth of Nations Smith's relatively modest goal is to demonstrate
the foolishness of many British tax and trade policies. The operational
foundations of England's international exchange system had become gravely
convoluted-often in response to the policies of other nations-and frequently
accomplished the exact opposite of what
192
was intended. In spite of his
somewhat narrow focus Smith knew he had to build a foundation to make his
case for change. In doing so he created a critical volume that has been
effectively applied across the globe and across the centuries. Today the
topic of trade couldn't be more timely. What Smith would think of modern
international tax and trade policies becomes self-evident as one reads his
criticisms; Wealth of Nations regains its status as a most effective
primer. He understood that what might appear as national self-interest,
which was far more rarely "enlightened" than personal
self-interest, was an impediment to rational economic policy. This was true
in his time and we see its effects yet today. Even though the jargon of
Smith's era did not include our "law of unintended consequences"
his insights reveal its timeless operation.
Certainly Smith wasn't the only bright or
perceptive person of his era. But one must wonder why he was nearly alone in
recognizing the pernicious quality of so much government intervention in the
marketplace. Most of the answer lies in the rigor of his efforts, which when
shaped by means of his intellectual acuity made Smith unique. He had an
ability to discern and differentiate between those policies that were the
causes of economic missteps and those that were just symptoms.
Wealth of Nations is difficult neither to
read nor comprehend. Its truths have withstood the tides of more than two
centuries of economic practice thus its value is well established. Applying
Adam Smith's eighteenth-century understanding to the two centuries of
economic battles following his era was accomplished in two thin volumes: The
Law (1850) by Frederic Bastiat and Economics
In One Lesson (1946) by Henry Hazlitt (Chapters 7 and 24
respectively). In these books the faith that is often placed in government
supervision and regulation is exposed as invariably counterproductive and
counterintuitive-but almost always politically useful.
Smith's detailed conclusions make Wealth of
Nations illuminating reading especially when we recall that he worked
and studied at a time when mass production and comprehension of the value of
the division of labor were in their infancy. Each scene in Smith's play
reflects a different segment
of economic activity. Smith starts with the division of labor and the
creation of the market and ends with basic concepts of international trade
and national taxation. His investigation proceeds with uniformly meticulous
attention to cause and effect so that the whole has a footing that easily
supports the structure.
193
The timelessness and utility of Smith's
observations may be seen in current political confrontations. It is also
visible in the history of U.S. political battles from 1929-when the Great
Depression began-to 1980 when the Reagan Revolution toppled what were
thought to be American political and economic verities. These former
"truths" turned out to be philosophical and psychological conceits
that had little correlation to human incentive or self-sufficiency. As we
re-read Smith in the twenty-first century it is obvious that the accuracy of
his commentary and his apprehensions regarding human nature have not been
tarnished since he first penned them. His lessons remain valuable today when
silly and even dangerous utopian notions of economic equality or political
direction of an economy can seem attractive, until their details and
consequences become evident.
About the Author
Adam Smith, whose father died before he was born in 1723, was raised in his
mother's world of Scottish gentry. He entered the University of Glasgow when
he was 14 and was at Oxford by the time he was 17. He remained at Oxford for
the next six years as a student and nascent professor. Upon graduation he
returned to Scotland and the University of Glasgow as a lecturer. There he
met and befriended David Hume (Scottish philosopher, economist, and
historian, 1711-1776). Smith's career took him to France for several years
as a tutor to the French court where he met many of Europe's economic and
political thinkers, including Voltaire (French dramatist and historian,
1694-1778). Smith began working on Wealth of Nations in 1766. It was
published in 1776 to significant scholarly and public acclaim. After Wealth
of Nations Adam Smith intended to write two philosophical overviews, one
on the theory and history of law, the other on the sciences and art. Smith
did not complete either of these works, and shortly before his death
inexplicably destroyed all of his manuscripts. After spending more than a
decade on his unfinished treatises while working as a Scottish customs
official, Smith died in 1790.
Available through:
Prometheus Books
Great Minds Series
59 John Glenn Drive
Amherst, NY 14228
800 421-0351
marketing@prometheusbooks.com
194 |