Originally published: 1960
411 pages | Chapter 14
THE CONSTITUTION OF
LIBERTY
Friedrich A. von Hayek |
When he wrote The Constitution of Liberty Friedrich von Hayek
intended to create an encyclopedic overview of how liberty is achieved in
the modern world. At the time he was composing, capitalism and socialism,
the two opposing economic systems then prevalent in the world, were in a
fight to the death. Individual freedom was inevitably tied to free-market
capitalism while collectivism was paired with socialism, thus in his
discussion of liberty he necessarily had to consider economic paradigms as
well.
One of the methods used in his investigation was to
encourage his readers look at common phenomena in a different light. He did
this in order to demonstrate how the painfully obvious can be hard to grasp
in an emotionally charged political atmosphere. He begins by examining the
origin of modern ideas underpinning the liberal view (in its modern
American, not classical European sense) of philosophy and economics. These
novel consequences of twentieth-century political maneuvering, such as the
development and power of the bureaucratic state, or legislation coined at
the behest of special interests, he sees as part of the intellectual
corruption of the governing purpose.
This volume is the second First Principles-reviewed
book authored by Hayek. In The Road to
Serfdom Hayek explains how and why collectivist socialist schemes of
governance cut against normal human impulses and are doomed to failure by
the very nature of their mechanisms. In the present treatise Hayek dissects
the fundamentals of liberty itself. What, exactly, is freedom? It seems a
simple enough concept but understanding its mechanisms requires more than a
superficial
205
perusal. Offering a defined alternative in the philosophical
arena to what he had deconstructed in the political arena in The Road to
Serfdom seemed necessary.
Beginning with an assessment of democracy as
discussed by John Locke and David Hume in the seventeenth and eighteenth
centuries, Hayek proceeds to examine its reality in the twentieth century.
First, he explores the concepts of separation of powers and of checks and
balances on the political side of the equation, and he finds that they are
essential because of the foibles of human nature. Then he considers why
these safeguards, which were designed to help remove arbitrariness from
governing, are undermined in the massive and essentially unchecked modern
bureaucracies that democracy has created. He argues that there are only two
antidotes to the bureaucratization of government: an independent judiciary
that can reign-in zealous regulators, and frequent open elections to keep
politicians within the structural bounds that had been set in democracy's
founding documents. Hayek states that an independent judiciary is
essentially the last line of defense against an expanding and often arrogant
bureaucracy. (In the twenty-first century we must consider if even this
bulwark may be insufficient as the judiciary becomes more and more
politicized, goal oriented, and as a result, increasingly disconnected from
Constitutional restraint.)
Hayek believes that any government that continues
to grow administratively and bureaucratically is merely trying to correct
the negative results of its last effort at ordering society by proclamation.
And in Hayek's view, democracies are only slightly less prone to using
dictatorial tactics in creating and administering their laws than
totalitarian societies are. The greatest danger is simply having good laws
administered badly. Hayek calls for dismantling any portion of government
that gets out of control either in terms of size or mission. He argues that
this is one of the most effective methods of reorganization. Even if the
department itself isn't abolished, when threatened with extinction
bureaucrats (like human beings everywhere) often offer change and revision
that make both good sense and good economics.
As well, Hayek takes a keen interest in ensuring
the executive side of government has its best chance at being honest. He
defines the necessity of a sharp separation of the law-making effort
conducted by the legislature-not the courts-from the application of policy
effected by administrative agencies. He conjectures that if the lawmakers
set rules that are applicable across the population, then, in theory,
administrators will not be able to apply those laws so as to discriminate
against
206
or in favor of subgroups or classes within the population.
Correcting abuses or errors in the execution of laws that might result from
an aggressive executive Hayek again sees as the province of an autonomous
judiciary. But he recognizes that only individual integrity will ultimately
allow the system to work. Corruption-especially the petty and frequently
rationalized intellectual kind, not fiscal thievery-is a barricade to sound
and fair governance. The U.S. Constitution and the American state were
designed for a moral people. The country could not be governed without this
foundation and Hayek sees individual morality, and action, as the antidote
to state corruption.
Hayek also reminds readers of the inherent value of
a written constitution: to express a body of rights that no legislature may
infringe. These rights are so fundamental that only the people themselves
may change them. With these basic rules embodied in a document, legislatures
and courts have guideposts to keep both policy and administration within the
bounds of equitable government. Hayek underscores the development of this
concept through his investigation of the contrasting histories of the
American and French Revolutions. He knew to fear temporary majorities (as
did James Madison and Thomas Jefferson) and he consequently regarded a
written constitution as essential.
Hayek observes that the differences between the
American Revolution of 1776 and the French Revolution of 1789 were based
upon each country's distinct views of mankind. These disparate conceptions
led to quite different historical outcomes. The contrasts are so important
and so core to understanding self-government that they are assessed in First
Principles by several authors.
The American Revolution aimed to secure personal
liberty; freedom from government as much as freedom for individuals. The
Founders later made this standard their goal as they designed our written
constitution. In France, the idea developed that power taken from the king
and the upper class would be placed in the hands of the people, all the
people, with the expectation that the people would naturally not abuse one
another. But unfortunately that is exactly what people do in the absence of
rules, no matter their station or education. They do this out of
self-preservation, not out of venality.
If there are no rules it is every person for himself, thus we see
self-protective, not simply selfish, behavior. The followers of Rousseau (the
pure democrats) wanted to tear down established methods and institutions
because they saw them as responsible for the corruption of human beings, not
vice versa. In theory, if the institutions were demolished man's natural
207
virtue would emerge. The French revolutionaries' unmodulated trust in the
citizenry thus doomed their government to failure. In contrast, the American
Founders' faith in a written constitution and laws better ordered natural
human inclinations by keeping potential despots from unrestrained power and
the populace from unrestrained self-interest. The people accepted submission to these rules, first, because they had written them, and second,
because if the rules did not work they could be changed through a democratic
process.
When the French revolutionaries wrongly assumed
that people would treat one another fairly and equitably pursuant to some
enlightened or utopian impulse to do so they were unfortunately only
reacting to the rule of the monarchy; they knew what they didn't want.
Through removal of their inept king they hoped to create in the people that
which they did want-a flowering of true brotherhood-Liberty, Equality,
Fraternity. However, man's first unrestrained (morally or
institutionally or by law) impulse is generally not toward equality or
generosity and thus the French model failed, gloriously and ignominiously.
The French learned that reasoned behavior and the civic culture necessary
for self-government must flow from set rules not facile assumptions or
hoped-for human behavior.
After considering fundamental concepts of how
government should be designed Hayek proceeds to examine equality-under the
law and as an objective for individuals in a just society. He recognizes
that unequal results in human achievement may tend to conjure simplistic
notions of injustice, especially in the discourse of judgmental and
self-aggrandizing demagogic politicians. In a society in which the dignity
of each person-not one's station, or employment, or one's accumulation of
goods-is the prime consideration, equality of opportunity can exist. Hayek
understood that only those who exploit human differences will distort the
idea of justice so that the goal of a just society is seen as equalitarian
(with a desire for equal results) rather than egalitarian (with a goal of
equal opportunity).
Hayek addresses individual inequalities from a
different angle. He asserts that equality is as undesirable as it is
unrealizable. Attempting to achieve the unattainable requires each of us to
forego who we are and what we can do in order to create something in which
no one ultimately believes-a society where everyone is the same and has the
same. He eventually arrives at the point of admonishing us against
equalitarianism not because people are selfish (although that is obviously a
part of human nature), but because individuals so differ with respect to
their talents
208
and ambitions. The outcomes of their efforts will reflect
their diversity and redound to the great benefit of everyone. Life is a
group of facts and a series of choices. The former limits the latter. Hayek
notes:
Let us by all means endeavor to increase opportunities for all. But we
ought to do so in the full knowledge that to increase opportunities for
all is likely to favor those better able to take advantage of them and
may often at first increase inequalities. Where the demand for
"equality
of opportunity" leads to attempts to eliminate "unfair
advantages," it
is only likely to do harm. All human differences, whether they are
differences in natural gifts or in opportunities, create unfair advantages.
But since the chief contribution of any individual is to make the best
use of the accidents he encounters, success must to a great extent, be
a matter of chance.
The core ideal of modern American liberalism is
equalitarianism-a theoretically noble but freighted and ultimately futile
goal. As no two human beings are equally fit for all tasks (and some are fit
for few tasks) achieving equal results can be attempted by fiat, but with no
prospect for success. As Hayek notes, because we cannot control any given
outcome even by decree, society is better off letting individuals freely
adjust. Expressing this without appearing anti-egalitarian (or, in the
twenty-first century, politically incorrect) is difficult; it requires some
attempt at discernment and sophistication by the observer. Often people
won't come to the truth without help. They get stuck at the start of their
reflections on inequality as they realize how putatively unjustly life
favors some persons with better chances, better foresight, or better
discipline. Plain old good luck is also a commodity that can no more be
eliminated than can good sense. That there are differences in circumstances
is a given: nature, planning, parents, and community have allowed some
people better opportunities. Yet even when opportunity does knock, many
cannot or will not open the door. Conversely, other people with seemingly no
advantages and myriad disadvantages attain incredible success. We cannot
take away the freedom to use the circumstances with which we are presented
unless all of us become automatons.
We also cannot take away anyone's success, no
matter how great or small, because to do so would be impractical, unjust,
and foolish. Would we discard all human progress because it comes from
humanity's unequal distribution of ambition, talent, and intellect?
209
Chance, whether genetic or circumstantial or both,
determines the place from which all of us start, but often goes unnoticed in
our day-to-day affairs. It inexorably operates as a social lever. As Hayek
notes, this seems so obvious, yet so difficult to grasp:
Liberty not only means that the individual has both the opportunity and
burden of choice. It also means he must bear the responsibility of his
actions. Liberty and responsibility are inseparable. Liberty, by definition,
also produces almost nothing but inequality in life, while demanding
equality of opportunity and treatment. From the fact that people are
inherently different it follows that, if we treat them equally they will
achieve unequal results, thus the only way to place them in an equal
position would be to treat them unequally.
Part of Hayek's overview focuses on the concepts
of Benthamism (utilitarianism-an attempt to achieve the greatest good for
the greatest number of people) in addition to the equalitarianism of the
French Revolution. He discusses the negative effects on liberty and
democratic principles encompassed in both philosophies. With profound
understanding he notes that it is "the French tradition, with its
flattering assumptions about the unlimited powers of human reason, that has
progressively gained influence." These assumptions about human reason
versus human action and experience (which time has repeatedly shown are
often not interchangeable) devolve into equally overconfident assumptions
about the value and validity of specific products of human reason-socialism,
equalitarianism, the welfare state. This is the theory: if we can think of a
perfect society, we must therefore be able to implement it. It is the vanity
of those who assume they know better than others (and want to control the
lives of others for their ostensible betterment) that causes so much
misdirection of the governing impulse.
Hayek observes that the English tradition is the
polar opposite of Benthamism (in spite of the fact that Jeremy Bentham was
British). English tradition was based on empiricism; that is, the practice
of deciding issues such as how a society will be governed by reference to
what works in the real world. Empiricism's opposite-rationalism-was the
foundation of the French Revolution. Rationalism assumes human beings can
think through a concept logically and then implement it
210
in that form,
irrespective of the human condition. As was obvious to Hayek, any society
formed by
imperfect human beings of widely varying natures, views, talents, and goals
will not fit well into some intellectual's view of what an individual's life
should be. The opposition of empiricism to rationalism has marked the fight
for liberty for more than two hundred years. The philosophical battles
raging today between American conservatives and their liberal and
neoconservative adversaries is a continuation of this struggle.
To combat socialist and social-welfare impulses
Hayek repeatedly emphasizes the importance of common democratic political
tools: separation of powers, frequent elections, an independent judiciary,
and checks and balances-all embodied in a written constitution. Hayek
explains that the absence of these tools (or our failure to implement them
consciously) enables the authoritarianism of planned societies and economies
to exist. Doomed to failure, rationalist authoritarian government suffers
from a fatal falsehood: its proponents deny the truth of the human
condition, including our inherent differences (which have led to all of the
world's material successes), and our intrinsic imperfectability.
Rationalists, assuming a perfectible population, know that they can
prove anything is possible, certainly anything as simple as creating the
economic foundations necessary to a sound society. Hayek investigates the
role government assumes in our economic relationships and how that
involvement affects both the social fabric and our individual liberty. In The
Constitution of Liberty Hayek explores every authoritarian fallacy. He
calmly disproves the conclusions arrived at by people who fail to comprehend
and deal with human nature as it is, rather than as they'd like it to be.
About the Book
The three indexes at the end of this University of Chicago Press edition of
Hayek's work are unique. One offers an index of subject matter, the second
is an index of authors, and the third (the most useful) is an analytical
index of the table of contents. The latter allows one to quickly scan the
political and philosophical content of Hayek's thoughts, and then go
directly to a discussion of particular interest.
211
About the Author
From economics (the field in which he won the Nobel Prize in 1974) to
psychology, history, anthropology, and science, Friedrich August von Hayek
amply demonstrated his intellectual abilities. In twenty-five books and
numerous articles he established the breadth and depth of his insights and
thoughts. Obviously he was no casual scholar. Born in 1899, he earned two
doctorates at the University of Vienna by the time he was 24. Hayek met his
intellectual partner, Ludwig von Mises, after his schooling was completed,
although both were in Vienna while Hayek was a student. Along with others,
Hayek and Mises eventually helped develop what became known as the Austrian
School of Economics. This system of economic thought denounced and then
intellectually dismantled socialism as a viable form of government or
economics. Hayek taught in London (1930-50), at the University of Chicago
(1950-62), and then again in Europe (1962-88) at the conclusion of his
teaching career. Although an economist by training and interest, Hayek took
a more fundamental view of the interconnections of society. His works, which
initially concentrated on economic matters, broadened in later years to the
point where he argued passionately for a liberal (free) society. In 1960 he
published The Constitution of Liberty, his treatise on classical
liberal political economy. Hayek died in 1992.
Available through:
University of Chicago Press
Chicago, IL 60637
www.uchicago.edu
212
|