Originally published: 1997
178 pages | Chapter
19
WHAT IT MEANS TO BE A
LIBERTARIAN
Charles Murray |
Opening a book that aims to analyze the relationship between individuals
and their government with a lengthy excerpt from Thomas Jefferson's first
inaugural address seems almost necessary. As the new president spoke of
individual freedom and our right to care for ourselves, he observed that
these were not quite enough to bring happiness. He noted that a wise and
frugal government was also necessary, one that "did not take from the
mouth of labor the bread it had earned." Jefferson was thinking, of
course, of the new government's power to tax (the power most hotly contested
during the Constitution's ratification battle).
Jefferson's understanding of human nature was
reflected in the precision with which he described the boundaries that
separated and the interdependence that linked governors to the governed.
That relationship is based upon the comprehension each must have of their
reciprocally reinforcing rights and duties. In the view of Charles Murray
and the Libertarian movement, fidelity to the Jeffersonian principle of
rights and duties is not just a definition of government, but its
very essence.
Murray begins his exposition of Libertarianism by
defining the goal of the Founders of the American system of governing:
limited central power and protection of individual rights. The dignity of
the individual and the integrity of every person's property and opportunity
are Murray's points of departure. He doesn't suggest that his readers will
misunderstand these ideas; he merely seeks to set the stage. Murray
259
takes
particular interest in where government and the governed actually fit
together at the dawn of the twenty-first century. From his perspective that
intersection is best defined by Libertarianism; implementing an active
libertarian philosophy in practice is his goal.
The difference between government and all the other
aspects of an individual's life is that people give government some power,
but not necessarily the absolute right, to use force to effect what appears
to be the consensus of the governed. The problem, Libertarians emphasize, is
that consensus is rarely reached. Murray asserts that the lack of such
accord should mean a corresponding reduction of action or intrusion on the
part of government. The logic of this conclusion seems in equal measure
inescapable and ignored. (For more on this point see Bertrand de Jouvenel's On
Power, Chapter 15.)
Politicians all too often act to the contrary of
Murray's hypothesis both while running for office and once elected. They
become infatuated with passing laws and/or implementing regulations that
deny the individual the right to engage in voluntary and informed
transactions. Those in power do this because of pressure from special
interests or their own hubris. They think they have been chosen to lead, so
they are going to do so; often they attempt to lead through their personal
sense of justice (or pique), which is not always fully shared by the
electorate at large. The bottom line for Libertarians, as reflected in the
essays of Lord Acton
(Chapter 9), is that the right of the individual to be free is a higher
right than any purpose of government, even a noble purpose. The conflict
often ceases to be a debate over whose nobility is more sacrosanct, that of
the person or that of the
collective. Instead, it becomes a struggle over power. In modern times, it
is the collective that has the edge for it automatically has most of the
power. Individuals are left with but one weapon-right.
Murray dissects government at its basic level. What
is the minimum amount of government needed? (That should be the maximum
allowed.) How may individuals best pursue that elusive concept of
"happiness" so succinctly articulated in the Declaration of
Independence? And, perhaps the most pressing question, what are our
responsibilities to ourselves, to our neighbors, and to the body politic?
The dividing line between the Libertarian approach
to governing and the more intrusive manner of today's liberal politicians is
the concept of equality. Libertarians start from a point of equal
opportunity and equal responsibility, whereas liberals aim at equal result
or condition. For the liberal, obtaining this equal result is the
responsibility of the
260
political class. Thus, not only is the starting point
remarkably different between Libertarians and liberals, their respective
views of human nature and the goal of government are also different.
The result is that in the eyes of each group government becomes a notably
different tool. In the one case, it is a minimalist effort embodying control
of legislative and bureaucratic excess while leaving the individual free to
live his own life. In the other case, government tends to be a substantially
enlarged interventionist effort to ensure equality for all. The latter in
its worst form moves toward a redistribution of wealth through a
confiscatory tax system that can-only initially and only briefly-produce a
more equalitarian society but which cannot produce equality. The eventual
economic result of such intervention is the reduction of incentives via
progressively higher taxes that then cause economic contraction, eventuating
in reduced living standards for almost everyone because of reduced economic
activity and opportunity. Obviously when market production declines the
government receives reduced tax revenue. A vicious cycle of tax increases to
offset lower tax collections repeats itself, with a concomitant reduction in
market activity. These actions unfortunately throw more people out of work,
which results in a call for even more government assistance, ad nauseum.
Society eventually operates on the basis of the lowest common denominator
rather than the highest. There is another unintended consequence as well:
almost invariably there arises a privileged and generally corrupt
arrangement favoring the redistributionist elite ensconced in government.
For Murray, the concept of freedom of thought,
choice, and action is fundamental. A person seeking to fully experience this
freedom must be responsible for himself and to others. Murray
makes an interesting conceptual note early in his definition of freedom by
stating,
Responsibility is not the "price" of freedom but its reward.
He asks the reader to think about what his most
enduring satisfactions have been. For most of us they will have been when we
were true to ourselves, our principles, and our moral judgments. That, for
Murray and all the Libertarians, is the essence of their philosophy. It is
an appealing outlook, especially when taken to its logical conclusion that
our socially relevant private activities (i.e., those that we individually
do for ourselves to avoid burdening others) determine our personal
satisfaction in life.
261
But Libertarians sometimes engage in a romantic
fantasy, that personal responsibility, which is the foundation of ordered
liberty, can be achieved across the population if government would just get
out of the way. That this is beyond the full capabilities of human beings is
self-evident, thus the
tension between Libertarianism and government itself is a never-ending
balancing act.
The assessments that Murray makes-using specific
examples of current and past government intervention-remain instructive,
thought provoking, and structurally helpful. His contention that in most
instances the good intentions of government are not realized makes one
wonder why we continue to tolerate so much government. Is the explanation
found in habit, lethargy, or the continued allure of hope in the face of
reality? Murray does not tell the reader how to act on these issues, but he
does make one think. His intention, of course, is that at the end of that
thought process we will arrive at the less government solution-the
Libertarian solution.
Murray's Libertarianism brings his readers back to
fundamental concepts and relationships. His program for more effective and
responsible governing-less is more-cannot be dismissed as some utopian ideal
because much of what he writes makes too much sense. For Murray and anyone
who thinks about it for a moment, government is not "they;" it is
"we." We must take responsibility for ourselves and the governing
paradigm we seek to create. Murray's work dovetails nicely with the classic
catch phrase, "We get the government we deserve." In other words,
if we devote too little time to governing ourselves, and if we think that
our responsibilities as citizens are completed when we put down our pencils
after marking our ballots, then we get bureaucrats and politicians who do
for us what they think we want and need, or worse, what they think we
should want or need. Murray seeks to change this thought process and
its results. A reordering of both government's publicly accepted goals and
its means toward those goals, he avers, could occur pursuant to our return
to the Founders' vision of minimal governmental intervention and maximum
personal responsibility and opportunity. If we take away the crutch
of government, then our society changes fundamentally for the better. That
is the goal of Libertarianism.
262
About the Author
Charles Murray is a resident fellow at the American Enterprise Institute in
Washington, D.C. Born in 1943 in Newton, Iowa, he earned his undergraduate
degree from Harvard in 1965 and then spent six years in Asia as a Peace
Corps volunteer and then as a researcher. Upon his return home he earned a
Ph.D. in political science in 1974 from MIT. His investigations into crime,
poverty, and social programs led him to write Losing Ground: American
Social Policy 1950-80. This book did much to set the tone of President
Ronald Reagan's domestic policy.
Murray's career as one of the nation's most influential conservative
thinkers is well established. He lectures and publishes widely and is a
frequent witness before congressional committees. Murray's most
controversial book, The Bell Curve: Intelligence and Class Structure in
American Life (with Richard Herrnstein) posits that wealth and other
positive social outcomes are a product of intelligence and that intelligence
is an innate characteristic that it is foolish to pretend either isn't
important or can be compensated for in some fashion (political or otherwise)
that eliminates the need to recognize its existence. Published in 1994, the
book caused a still-continuing social debate.
Available through:
Broadway Books
Div. of Bantam Doubleday Dell
1540 Broadway
New York, NY 10036
www.randomhouse.com
263 |