Originally published: 1942
425 pages | Chapter
38
CAPITALISM, SOCIALISM AND DEMOCRACY
Joseph A. Schumpeter |
The ability of a specialist to keep in mind the big picture while
concentrating on his smaller arena is crucial to the overall value of his
work. Joseph Schumpeter had such a talent, even though the conflicts he
faced in the larger world sometimes caused him to doubt the conclusions to
which his work led. His individual field was the economics of business;
however, to make sense in that domain he had to understand how the public
economy and the body politic broadly adapted to one another and to myriad
additional considerations. His ability to comprehend both perspectives and
dissect them for the reader is what makes his works so valuable on the broad
plain of social discourse.
Schumpeter's discernment of business cycles and how
they work-periods of stasis that alternate with growth or contraction-formed
the basis of modern economic prediction and management. Though his ideas
seem routine and even elementary today, in Schumpeter's era they were novel
and untested. While developing his entrepreneurial economic paradigms,
Schumpeter's talent for seeing the horizon led him to write Capitalism,
Socialism, and Democracy. When he drafted his thesis, no one was sure,
including Schumpeter himself, which economic system-capitalism or
socialism-was more viable either practically or politically, and there was
great debate within the social disciplines.
Schumpeter begins his analysis with an
investigation of communism as envisioned by Karl Marx (1818-1883). Marxism,
explained in The Communist Manifesto (1848), was still evolving at
mid-twentieth century and just being tested in the real world. Schumpeter
concludes that
457
the Marxist system is chimerical, dishonest, and
dissociative. Sharing President Abraham Lincoln's belief in the
impossibility of fooling all the people all the time Schumpeter asserts that
the economic folly of communism would cause it ultimately to fail-wholly,
and with great noise. His real query is the other side of the economic
question; whether capitalism could succeed and if its adjunct, democracy,
could meet the challenge of governing the world's many interrelated
minorities (whether that be one and half billion Muslims spread among 40
nations or 4 million Zulus as a population fraction inside South Africa).
These were legitimate questions in the first half of the twentieth century
and they continue to remain relevant in the twenty-first where the fledgling
economies of the Third World (including rapidly modernizing China and India)
are just beginning to enter the free market and freedom itself is still
largely miscomprehended.
Schumpeter turns Marx and his economic
predilections inside out; not just because it was easy to do but because it
was necessary. Marx was venerated by the heirs of the Enlightenment-the
newly minted socialist equalitarians of the twentieth century-but their
veneration could not trump reality.
Schumpeter explains part of his critique of Marx by
means of Marx's personal background and social environment which he then
uses to dissect Marx's political and economic import. Schumpeter notes that
Marx had no country having been displaced from Germany to France to England.
Marx thus thought that no one else needed a homeland, or really, even a
home, and so his utopian vision
was largely a reflection of his myopian viewpoint. Yet Schumpeter finds that
Marx felt unsettled in each country because of more than just personal
experience. Marx was dissatisfied with the world because he, like Vladimir
Ilyich Lenin after him (the leader of the 1917 Russian Revolution that
resulted in the imposition of a communist state in the vast Russian
landmass), found something wrong with everything. At the same time he quite
incongruously insisted that perfection was possible, as seen in his
idealized ordering of society by means of his communist fantasy. The
disconnection between fact and fiction, their views and their goals, and the
inherent futility of their means never seemed to bother either man.
Schumpeter, after offering his own summary of
Marx's economic theorizing, directs his most derisive scorn at Marx's
contention that socialistic democracy was of a different ilk than bourgeois,
capitalistic democracy. The fact that "democratic socialism" was
an oxymoron-both by definition and as a philosophical precept-was
458
but a
beginning point to dismember Marx's political assertions. That democratic
socialism achieves oxymoronic status can be demonstrated in syllogistic
fashion: the foundation of a free society is based equally in the
individual's natural right to own property and in his right to freedom of
thought and action. A free society is one democratically controlled by the
thoughts and actions of the people. Socialist theory denies the validity of
both private property and the concurrent right of the people to govern
themselves; thus a society cannot be democratic and socialistic
simultaneously.
The phrasing-democratic socialism-was a ruse to
mislead and calm the public into thinking they actually had a hand in
utopian constructions that would work in the real world. The ultimate proof
of the anti-democratic nature of socialism was the fact that when elections
did occur in a collectivist environment, only one name appeared on the
ballot for each office, and that candidate was imposed on the people, not
publicly selected. When this false democracy was offered it was purely and
obviously a subterfuge, a means of deflecting reality. Of course, the fact
that in a socialistic setting distribution of society's products must be
controlled in a totalitarian fashion because public agreement on such
matters is not possible (it must be remembered that individuals have opinions)
deconstructs with finality any pretensions of freedom.
Once Schumpeter dissects Marxism he turns to a
consideration of capitalism. One of his goals is to encourage his readers to
think horizontally and vertically; to consider, for example, that the
economic and social opening of India or Japan, a political feat, is perhaps
less important than the conquest of the air or the airwaves. He wonders, as
well, if geographic frontiers are less of an impediment to progress than
economic boundaries. For example, does the lack of free-markets hold back an
economy more than the unavailability of natural resources? (The answer is
yes, and for illustration look at what free markets have done for resource
starved Japan, Hong Kong, Switzerland or Israel and what a lack of freedom
has accomplished in resource rich nations such as those in southern Africa.)
These were relatively sophisticated considerations
that few economists up to that point had investigated. At the close of every
great epoch, Schumpeter notes, it is rare that people can see the future,
but the future is exactly where they should focus. His intention in this
book is to expose the competing political and economic elements that he
sees-the elements that define how the future will play out.
459
In looking forward Schumpeter sees capitalism as
the propelling force in the rationalization of human behavior. Think about
that concept: the rationalization of human behavior. He steps back a
few centuries and observes that the commercial impetus to rational conduct
was clearly operative in the Middle Ages when business transactions founded
primarily but not exclusively in the division of labor were a key element in
the demise of feudalism. The landed aristocracy slowly discerned they could
make more money in "business," such as it was, than solely by
overseeing their serfs' agricultural activities.
In his investigation Schumpeter underscores how
pragmatic economics always and everywhere influences all facets of human
endeavor. (Ludwig von Mises's much expanded philosophical and practical
examination of this concept can be found in Human
Action [Chapter 40]. The theories of both men are extrapolations
that have an unstated but basic foundation in mankind's quest to ensure
self-preservation-i.e., food, shelter, etc.-that causes human beings to act
in a rational manner.) Schumpeter maintains that the viability of the
capitalistic process, including freedom of individual action, must be
included in any assessment of how far and how successfully a culture has
progressed toward both liberty and sound economic behavior. For Schumpeter
the important effect for social progress wasn't just capitalism's mandate of
fundamentally rational activity, it was also capitalism's demand to measure
everything that was happening that was so valuable. For example, capitalism
brought logic and math into the lexicon of the ordinary sixteenth-century
peasant trying to determine if he should sell his cow, and if what he was
being offered was at least equal to the value of the cow-to him. The element
of judgment in this small example and also in every aspect of capitalistic
enterprise is a valuable tool for a simple reason: it fosters progress
across the spectrum of human activity through the use of discrimination and
critical evaluation.
After delineating his economic assessment of
capitalism and socialism Schumpeter turns to the realities of practical
politics and history's conventions. He hedges his denunciation of
socialism's chance to become the world's dominant economic system. He does
not equivocate with regard to socialism itself-he knows that it is not
viable, but that simple fact in his view did not ensure that socialistic
practice would soon die on the vine. (His temporizing on this subject led to
his ambiguous standing among well-known economists for many decades.) As a
result of the times (he was writing just after the Great Depression and
during World War II) and the state of the public's less-than-benevolent
460
perception of free enterprise because of the fiscal and social disaster that
had transpired during the 1930s, he was concerned that even more government
intervention in the economy would be seen as the answer to what had
theoretically impeded economic recovery around the world during the twenty
years prior to the publication of his book; i.e., too little intervention.
Schumpeter knew bureaucratic or political intrusion
wasn't what was needed in a situation such as the Depression, indeed, he
understood these were decidedly what was not needed. Schumpeter was more
than aware that government intervention-meaning high taxation, burdensome
regulation, trade barriers, and deficit spending-had caused the Depression
to last longer and affect the world's economies more deeply than would have
been the case if the free market had been allowed to independently regain
its footing. Many economists were led to accept the political thought that
socialism, with its wholesale government control of all economic
fundamentals, could be seen as the answer to what didn't work in the 30s.
The fact that Schumpeter understood socialism's
systemic failings, rooted primarily in the suppression of individual
incentive and reward (and the obvious reasons for its political success-the
free lunch it offered) did not, by default, make democracy the answer to the
question: what system of government will achieve the dual goals of
individual freedom and economic progress? In the real
world, Schumpeter sees democracy as less than wholly successful exactly
because of what many of the world's democracies had experienced over the
previous century (ubiquitous economic depressions, civil wars, capitalistic
oppression, etc.). He is especially concerned about the viability of
democratic rule in the context of a "mixed" population or when the
times create highly confrontational divisions:
Whenever . . . principles are called in question and issues arise that rend
a nation into two hostile camps, democracy works at a disadvantage. And
it may cease to work at all as soon as interests and ideals are involved on
which people refuse to compromise.
The extreme possibility of suggesting civil war
or political division arises infrequently in a mostly homogenous society;
but in a blended commonwealth war has occurred more often than those who
believe in democracy's efficacy like to recall. Schumpeter's recognition of
this
461
potential, in 1942 in the middle of a worldwide military conflict, is
not unexpected but may contain more pessimism than was warranted. Yet what
Schumpeter felt the world faced was the possibility of one of two very
unpleasant eventualities: democracy would lead to civil conflict because
various (ethnic, cultural, social, language, tribal) minorities could not
agree on fundamental choices and would rather fight than give in; or,
totalitarianism would be seen as the way to avoid internecine conflict but
would destroy humanity's individual freedoms. (The effects of the minority
intransigence that worried Schumpeter are seen most starkly today in those
countries cobbled together by the Great Powers as political acts after World
Wars I and II. The Balkans and Iraq, of course, come quickly to mind, but
many of the countries in Africa and Asia mired in a Third World mentality
fit this profile as well.) Schumpeter thinks socialism, which is ultimately
totalitarian, might look better in spite of its destruction of freedom than
ever-present, ever-recurrent conflict. He thinks people might see this
choice-security without freedom-as the eventual solution. Freedom without
security-in light of both the Depression and World War II-Schumpeter thinks
might be more than humanity could face.
Time has shown that having faith in the upside of
the human condition (its continued striving toward change for the better, in
other words, its ability to discriminate between what is good and what is
not, what will work and what will not) rather than certainty as to its
downside (human perfidy, fear, or selfishness) is more than justified. The
pessimism that Schumpeter offers is more a reflection of his very unsettled
and difficult era-perhaps the most contentious of the twentieth century-than
long-term political reality.
What that observation refers to is this: throughout
First Principles we have noted the negative effects of the human condition,
how it can often work against well-intentioned and even good theoretical
designs or some form of benevolent ordered liberty. We have done that only
with the intention of explaining (in a somewhat shorthand fashion) why a
mostly well-designed government doesn't always result in a well-oiled and
smooth-functioning society. But in Schumpeter's case we also have to equally
recall the beneficial potential of the human spirit-that it does covet order
and freedom in a context of rationality. Conflict, confrontation, and war
are sometimes necessary tools in an attempt to force rationality (recall
Walter McDougall's observation in Promised
Land, Crusader State [Chapter 20], "force sometimes precedes
reason"), but are not conditions under which one can live permanently.
462
Thus the upside of the human condition, the human spirit, incites a drive to resolution and ultimately peace-so long as such are ultimately
achieved through voluntary agreement and not by force.
At the end of World War II (which not only wasn't
in sight when Schumpeter published his treatise but which was proceeding
favorably for the Axis Powers [Germany, Italy, and Japan]) he expected the
socialist order (or at least central planning if not centralized control of
the economy) to be more entrenched than ever. Although he knew socialism's
goals could not be achieved by socialism's methods, he bases his expectation
of its ascendancy on the Great Depression's stimulus to enlarged government
oversight and intervention in economic and social matters and the
war-induced economic centralization in both the Allied and Axis camps. He
sees the expansion of central planning and control that had begun in the
1930s as virtually unstoppable. Accordingly, he predicts the likely triumph
of, at least, socialistic practices over capitalism-not because socialism
was superior but because it was already in place to a considerable extent
and because the times and personalities would allow its further
entrenchment. In other words, Schumpeter comes to his conclusions based on
practical expectations-a social or humanistic assessment-and foregoes his
own well-argued faith in the demands of rationality in economic enterprise.
Schumpeter believes that a docile population cannot
prevail against those in power who would implement the peacetime conversion
(no matter which side won), demand primary control, and justify their
actions by claiming that what had worked in wartime would continue to work
in peace. He also believes that such leaders would frighten people into
thinking they knew what they were doing by suggesting that no one would want
to return to the chaos and poverty of the 30s. The prediction of socialism's
dominance was based on "extrapolating observable tendencies" not
on a lack of faith in our ability to formulate intellectual and practical
arguments against such a system of governance.
Initially, certainly, Schumpeter's predictions were
correct; at the end of the war Great Britain, the cradle of free democracy
and market capitalism, not only installed a socialist government, but turned
out of office Winston Churchill, their war-time prime minister, who was
seen, literally, as the country's savior. Churchill had not only predicted
the coming war as early as 1933, he had led England through its darkest
hour; his exalted status achieved through respect for his prescient
463
intellect and dogged determination in war should have been secure but he
decried socialism in all its contortions-and the British public again
ignored him and his advice as they had in 1933. At that point Schumpeter's
expectations became reality.
However, in spite of the British experience
Schumpeter's fears were ultimately proven ephemeral. In his examination of
"observable tendencies" he seems to have overlooked the fact or
even the possibility that what the citizenry was willing to cede to the
government during times of war was not necessarily that to which it would
acquiesce over the long term in peacetime. He also seems to have erred by
focusing on humankind's single-mindedness in war, a mental state that
broadens to become expansive, multi-faceted imagination in times of peace.
People tend not to countenance interventionism when it is not mandatory for
survival. One is reminded particularly, when reviewing Schumpeter's reasoned
concern about the future, of John Maynard Keynes's injunction regarding the
force of ideas:
The power of vested interests is vastly exaggerated compared with the
gradual encroachment of ideas.
Despite the sometimes pessimism and ultimate
inaccuracy of his predictions, the breadth and depth of Schumpeter's
investigations in this book and the supporting history he recounts are
simply awesome. His exposition of socialism's weaknesses, and failures, laid
a foundation for future writers and economists who studied the political
centralization of public purposes in all its guises. Therein lay the
continuing value of Schumpeter's investigations. It is not that widespread
socialism is likely to revive anytime soon, but collectivism and
totalitarianism are both still alive, and could gain acceptance-especially
in the Islamic and Third Worlds where fundamentalist religious or social
constructs are still the rule. With these possibilities extant, having
knowledge of the past and pragmatically based counter-arguments prepared to
stifle its repetition are necessary.
Understanding that someone as incisive and
brilliant as Schumpeter won't get everything right every time, while
appreciating the incalculable value of those things that he does predict
accurately, is useful in approaching the comprehensive explorations of the
authors who helped shape the modern world. It is not easy to convince human
beings that freedom is first among equals and more necessary than security,
that without freedom there is no security. If a society does not have
464
the
ability and the will to change what goes wrong-and invariably something goes
wrong-then that society can only become totalitarian or anarchic. Watching
all of the theorists and philosophers presented throughout First
Principles struggle in the attempt to not only make that case but prove
it is seen in the writing of Joseph Schumpeter.
For Schumpeter and others the seemingly
overwhelming real-world facts of their times caused misjudgment of the
capability of human striving. The long-term effect of distorted reality on
human behavior and sound theory is still not as powerful as the human
spirit. In spite of the fact that the real world is at intervals temporarily
wrong, even insane, it generally rights itself although sometimes in
devastating fashion. In other words, sometimes people die, and are willing
to die, to recreate a rational world. And that is exactly what happened
during the second half of the twentieth century. But that experience was not
so clearly seen from the vantage point of 1942-thus Schumpeter's sometimes
pessimism in Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy.
Schumpeter's work has an intellectual reach that
demands the reader engage in the debate on every level and with respect to
all particulars. Understanding Schumpeter's dark view regarding the
ascendancy of socialism-in spite of that system's inherent and fatal
failings-and then viewing the course of history subsequent to Schumpeter's
stated fears, where freedom and individuality again became the norm, offers
continued hope in the ability of human society to right itself-but almost
always with great effort, constant vigilance, and many unintended
consequences.
About the Author
Having earned a doctorate at a young age, Joseph Schumpeter became known as
"the genius without a knack for success." Born in 1883 in what is
now Slovakia, he was only four when his father died. Schumpeter went on to a
brilliant early career in academia yet, in spite of many opportunities to
succeed, he was unable to turn them into palpable accomplishments.
Regardless of the fact that Schumpeter was a polymath and fluent in six
languages, his intellectual talents failed to prevent his real-world
dismissal from his post as Finance Minister of Austria and later as a
private banker, mostly because he was in the wrong place at the wrong time.
Yet his books on economics
inspired others to investigate his subject matter on a broader scale than
had been done before. During his career at Harvard University, where he
465
began teaching in 1932, he formed the basis of his economic and more broadly
theoretical works, thereby laying the groundwork for advanced investigations
by him and others into economic theory and practice. Late in his career,
when his academic accomplishments advanced his reputation, he served as
president of both the Econometric Society, which he helped found, and the
American Economic Association. Schumpeter died in 1950.
Available through:
Harper & Row Publishers, Inc.
10 E. 53rd St.
New York, NY 10022
www.harpercollins.com
466
|